Fundamental Rights: The Right to Have Rights
ISBN: 978-1-80117-994-2, eISBN: 978-1-80117-990-4
Publication date: 11 November 2024
Citation
Mazzola, D. (2024), "Fundamental Rights: The Right to Have Rights", Freedom and Borders, Emerald Publishing Limited, Leeds, pp. 11-69. https://doi.org/10.1108/978-1-80117-990-420241002
Publisher
:Emerald Publishing Limited
Copyright © 2025 Dario Mazzola. Published by Emerald Publishing Limited. This work is published under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY 4.0) licence. Anyone may reproduce, distribute, translate and create derivative works of this work (for both commercial and non-commercial purposes), subject to full attribution to the original publication and authors. The full terms of this licence may be seen at http://creativecommons.org/licences/by/4.0/legalcode.
License
This work is published under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY 4.0) licence. Anyone may reproduce, distribute, translate and create derivative works of these works (for both commercial and non-commercial purposes), subject to full attribution to the original publication and authors. The full terms of this licence may be seen at http://creativecommons.org/licences/by/4.0/legalcode.
The representatives […] have resolved to set forth, in a solemn Declaration, the natural, unalienable and sacred rights of man. –Declaration of Human and Civic Rights of 26 August 1789
We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men […] are endowed [..] with certain unalienable Rights. –The Declaration of Independence
Natural rights is simple nonsense: natural and imprescriptible rights, rhetorical nonsense -nonsense upon stilts. –Jeremy Bentham 1
There are no such rights, and belief in them is one with belief in witches and unicorns.
–Alasdair MacIntyre 2
2.1 What Is a Right?
Citizenship seems intuitively distinct from rights for at least two reasons. The former is that, in this age, rights have been unbundled from the framework of the nation-state, as the expression “human rights” itself suggests. The latter is that the notion of rights, both at the local and universal level, has been thus represented as unproblematic to displace any in-depth discussion of it from the context of debates over the nature and form of citizenship. In this work, both assumptions are reversed. Citizenship is considered not in opposition, but on a continuum between the local or national level and the human or universal one. And respectively, the concept of “right” is recognized in all its complexity and problems, in a way that makes it impossible for a notion of citizenship to rest securely on it without calling it into question.
It is here possible to draw a parallel between rights and citizenship. To say that both go unquestioned in daily life is an understatement. People cheer for the national team and suppose, even require others to be inflamed by patriotic passions as they see the national colors. 3 People invoke rights and are angered when they see these ignored or violated. How are these rights defined? It is hard to say. A supporter of the Second Amendment claimed to me that the reason why “the right to keep and bear guns” should not be questioned is that “it is a right: if you take it away, what else are you seizing next?” This example from a trivial conversation displays with remarkable ingenuity the circularity of the argument: rights are sacred because[…] they are rights. Likewise, the quintessential importance of citizenship and nationality – the two terms will be used interchangeably here – is rooted just in that: that nationality is sacred. Both are hard to spell out. Americans want to see “America First.” But why? And what is “America” and who belongs to it? Likewise, rights ought to be respected. But why? And how are they defined? Wherefrom are they taken, in other words?
The connection between the two questions will become clearer as we reflect on the classic definition of citizenship as an assemblage of rights (and duties) and will notice that citizenship is usually and normally the main legal cum political cum social device to implement them.
However, this book will not provide a definite answer to the question of “what is a right” or where rights come from. This is for a number of reasons, in order of relevance.
First, the question could be itself misconstrued: as we will see, entire civilizations have been built and thrived without the concept of a “right,” and this has been the case in the classic eras of Western civilization as well.
Second, a theory of morality and justice would lead us astray from the inquiry into the nature of citizenship, while a preliminary and limited consideration of its problems needs not.
Third and finally, under the conditions of value pluralism and ideological diversity we find in Western societies, and above all, with the perspective of global or world citizenship that is taken in this work, any answer, no matter how sound, that can be provided – indeed included the many sound answers that have been provided – is bound to be rejected on this or that perspective. A question more fitting to this inquiry is as follows: “What conception of rights is workable, how should we understand rights to put them to use under these conditions of radical value pluralism and cultural diversity?”
When we speak of a pragmatic, or implementable, conception of rights, it is necessary to further qualify this objective: what is needed is a conception that has some employment, but one should not be overoptimistic about the weight that can be exerted by it. In looking for it, two different directions need to be explored. The former is the status quo of the debate over rights. The latter is a number of acquisitions about and around rights that while falling short of yielding a closing answer to the question of “what is a right” do indeed help to bring it into focus.
2.1.1 The Form of Rights
The formal structure and definition of rights are perhaps the most solid springboard from within a debate where everything is contestable. This should offer at least a general matrix into which the question of citizenship, like many others, can be translated. Furthermore, any indication we can gain about the structure of rights should constrain answers to more substantial questions, in the same way as the description of a shell or a dwelling can reveal something about the content or the inhabitant. This formal inquiry is of course still open to the radical objection – uselessness/emptiness – that comes with the rejection of the very idea of a right to be considered later on.
A formal description of the kind we are looking for has been offered by the American jurist and legal philosopher Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld approximately one century ago, as he published his seminal essay on Fundamental Legal Conceptions in 1919.
Rights are entitlements (not) to perform certain actions, or (not) to be in certain states, or entitlements that others (not) perform certain actions and/or (not) be in certain states. 4
We will leave aside the problem of clarifying what “entitlements” are as the term is hopefully more self-explanatory than right. All rights can be described as “Hohfeldian incidents,” that is, they pertain to one of the categories helpfully clarified by Hohfeld and named after him. 5
The simplest of these incidents is the privilege, namely an exemption from a general duty. It can be written in a general form such as
“A has a Y right to phi” implies “A has no Y duty not to phi”. 6
Examples of privileges are police carrying guns and border guards asking for documents, or, to come to our subject, the statement “Citizens have a general legal and moral right to return to their own country without a visa,” where this means that they have no legal or moral duty not to do so.
The second Hohfeldian incident is the claim, which is correlative to an obligation of someone toward the person who bears the right in question: 7
“A has a Y right that B phi” implies “B has a Y duty to A to phi”.
In this way, we say that “Citizens have a right to be provided help and information by their embassy when they are undergoing special difficulties abroad,” or we make the complementary (technically speaking: “correlative”) statement that “Embassies have a duty to support their own nationals when these are under circumstances of special needs.” Most ordinarily, very young children unquestionably have legal and moral claim rights to be taken care of by their parents and/or guardians and tutors: these imply correlative duties on the part of the latter.
These two simplest or “first-order” Hohfeldian incidents share the linguistic forms of the “second-order” incidents, the entitlements that alter the normative situation of oneself or another: that is, what oneself or another has an entitlement to be, do, or be done to. The “second-order” incidents are in turn divisible into powers and immunities.
The general form of powers is the following: “A has a Y right to phi.” As we have just seen, this is the form of a privilege, but it indicates a power if by “phi” we mean to “change the rights and duties within a set of rules.” Namely, “Joe has a moral/legal right to establish and/or waive rights and duties for Julie” is an example of a power: simply, in this scenario, and quite similarly to ordinary parlance, “Joe has power over Julie.” Two parents have a moral and legal power to forbid their child from eating candies, within the set of rules that regulates parenting within any given society. As a consequence of their decision, the child would therefore lose the privilege to eat candies. Citizens have the legal power to vote for someone in a national election and thereby assign her the power to restrict or widen the requirements for naturalization, through her work in the legislature and within the limits set by the constitution.
In this last example, two powers are implied: the citizens' altering their representative's power by electing her to be a representative and the latter's power to participate in lawmaking which affects the citizens in turn. Note, however, that the “right to vote” signifies the privilege to express one's political preference, which does translate into power only under certain conditions – such as those required for a voted candidate to be elected. These intricacies – associations, overlaps, uncertainties, and ambiguities – are common in the analysis of rights and make confusion on the matter very likely, already on a purely formal perspective. Hohfeld provided a partial antidote: yet if his language might prove sophisticate even in court, applying it in everyday discussions is often utopian.
Moving on to the last Hohfeldian incident: the general form of immunities is in turn formally the same as that of claims. “A has a Y right that B phi.” An immunity consists of the right (and the correlated duties) that someone's normative situation within a set of rules is not altered: for example, female citizens in many advanced democracies hold an immunity from being disenfranchised by virtue of their countries' constitutions.
It is difficult to come up with a right claim that falls beyond the reach of the Hohfeldian scheme: thanks to its lights, it became possible to recognize and signal the continuous switches in the meaning of the word “right,” but as noted, Hohfeld's antidote was not a panacea. Any attempt at analyzing a right should nonetheless requires much effort and patience because of the complexity of our morals, our laws, our society, and our language. For instance, the right a mother has to decide the diet of her young child would involve constitutional immunity from having a particular kind of upbringing imposed by the state, the power to delegate the care of the child to relatives, schools, nurses, and nannies, the legal and moral duties not to threaten the health of infants by irresponsible choices and so forth.
The interconnectedness, richness, and complexities of rights, duties, and the institutional and conceptual cantilever and scaffolding can get vertiginous. In the past, I have argued that the apparently uncomplicated claim that refugees have rights implies a political conception of the international community that would have been deemed revolutionary for centuries in the long history of modern nation-states. 8
Citizenship rights work like any other, and from a legal point of view, they connect the “ordinary” political authority of the community that enforces them to the multilayer legislation of international institutions and agreements. For example, a state of the EU must take into account national laws, standards agreed on by all the members of the Union and international treaties that reach even wider. Occasionally to regularly, it is of course problematic to understand what norms are in fact rights (and duties) and how rights should be ordered and applied: this is the everyday job of courts, and sometimes also a task for governments, parliaments, committees, and other such bodies. Beyond the legal sphere, moral rights can be no less pressing: a classic case in point is Antigone, Sophocles' play in which the protagonist is torn between the legal obligations against her brother, who has become a public enemy, and the moral obligations toward him. The story illustrates clashes between the legal and the moral, the personal and the political, the local and the universal (as “natural law” is supposedly borderless) at one time. Some theorists speak of prima facie rights to refer to the number of obligations that have to be taken into account at first sight but must be ordered and either enforced or trumped upon consideration. For instance, during a medical emergency, it is usually possible to drive in a way that would ordinarily be forbidden, and a state emergency can suspend or alter a large body of legislation, including immunities, as COVID-19 has shown.
Hohfeld and the scholars that followed him shaped an all-embracing tool for analyzing situations in which rights are disputed, and for clearing up their composite meaning, but this step toward the harmonization of moral and legal conflicts is far from being conclusive. Beyond the practical problem of reducing the complexity of aggregated, “molecular” rights, questions about rights' proper function remain theoretically as biting.
2.1.2 The Function of Rights
It is apparent that, despite its utility and range, what has been provided so far is more of a description than a definition: we know that rights are Hohfeldian incidents, but we still lack a most important exclusion of the Hohfeldian incidents that are not rights. Every whim and extravagant claim can be translated into Hohfeldian terms. The theory reported so far is inclusive and not exclusive, but the question of linguistic structure and substantive content must be asked independently. All dolphins are mammals, but not all mammals are dolphins: likewise, Astolfo's right to ride the hippogriff to the moon is certainly well construed in Hohfeldian terms, and based on the fiction, we might wonder whether it is a privilege, claim, power or immunity but what distinguishes this bogus construct – as well as any invalid right – from a genuine one?
On this matter, the wide to unanimous agreement one encounters when pondering the general convenience and applicability of the Hohfeldian account fades. Many have tried to give a further contribution by identifying one or more common features, but the debate is still ongoing and after about a century it seems impossible to secure stably any notable improvement, to the point that the very terms in which the question is posed are sometimes challenged.
There is a set of thus-called “monistic theories,” meaning the theories that aspire to single out just one essential element as constitutive of a right. The most important theories in the field, at least in recent years, argued for the defensibility of one or the other comprehensive principle.
The will theory, in particular, focuses on the choice that a right gives to an individual entitled to it. The right-holder is in this perspective a “small sovereign” capable of limiting other people's wills through her decision. 9 It is already apparent from this interpretation that rights are directly connected to sovereignty and especially to freedom, as well as to propriety. Indeed, claim rights are often considered the paradigmatic form of rights, and propriety rights offer either a model or a historical source for rights in general. Per the “will theory,” one's choice (an alternative name of the will theory is “choice theory”) establishes duties for others. While sovereignty and freedom are key elements of this research, and it is, therefore, appropriate to stress their relationship and analogy to individual rights thus represented, neither the “will theory” nor its alternative is endorsed by the perspective put forward here.
The main rival for the will theory is the interest theory, which is based upon an assumption that is just as concise and straightforward: rights have the essential function of promoting someone's interests. Of course, this statement too must be analyzed carefully because no interest can constitute automatically a right. The development of interest theories has paid much attention to the problem of distinguishing what kind of interests has a normative relevance, and, conversely, which interests generate only prima facie rights that can be trumped by other norms. 10
Behind the language of a “will” or “choice” theory of rights sometimes lies a normative assumption that is coupled with the descriptive analysis of the word “right”'s ordinary usage, but some argue that both theories should be in themselves “neutral” 11 in this respect.
There are also numerous and diverse pluralistic accounts of rights, as opposed to the main “monistic” ones recalled thus far. Pluralistic accounts tend to accept the complex and diverse set of normative phenomena ordered by Hohfeld rather than trying to reorganize or restrict them. Leif Wenar's “several functions” theory of rights matches the Hohfeldian incidents with a set of specific functions each one of them could perform, like exemption, protection, authorization, and so on. Hohfeldian incidents are thus taken to be rights only when they effectively play one or more of such roles.
Reaching even further, the “any-incident” theory of rights plainly suggests that all Hohfeldian incidents are rights. In this way, the problem becomes not that of distinguishing between incidents those which are actually rights but rather that of understanding the interaction between all these incidents.
Even if one of these theories turned out to be victorious, and achieved an endorsement as wide as the Hohfeldian formal scheme, the questions concerning the eventual normative validity of a single right would still be far from being fully answered. To wit: let us assume that the “interest theory” prevails. It is unclear whether any specific version of it would suffice to discriminate a normatively valid interest, say a private individual's interest in not having their government choose their partner, from an illegitimate one, say a thief's interest not to be investigated against. Any attempt at thus bridging a general theory of rights with its specific and detailed applications will necessarily turn into a general philosophy and view of society: and a normative loaded and specific one at it.
No one of these theorists is close, at least for the moment, to furnishing us with a practical test to distinguish between false and valid pretensions of having such and such rights. Each of them could be tempted to reply that as a part of his\her theory, there is in fact something similar to the test or the formula we are looking for, or some hint to it, but the sheer extent of the variations and differences between theories, and within theories, undermines the hope that this optimism is justified.
Neither the form nor the function of right is in and by itself a reason for its relevance and validity. Showing that a function is performed is one thing, and vindicating the legitimacy or effectiveness of such performance is quite another.
It must also be recognized that these theories have all arisen as ex-post interpretations, explanations, and perhaps even rationalizations of the conception of rights. The history and development of the general concept and its specific conceptions are relatively independent of them all.
Initially, I felt like this skeptical view was extreme and scarcely represented in the literature. 12 Yet about a decade after having first conceived it I see that first, no one theory of rights has emerged from the arena as triumphant, and second, David Frydrych has articulated the very same criticism in recent articles. 13
What are we to do with all these theories, then? I believe the reply to be fourfold.
First, as suggested, the pluralistic and, to some extent, relativistic, arbitrary, and even accidental nature of what can come to constitute a “right” under specific circumstances should be recognized. The consequence is that of abandoning any attempt at providing a unitary neutral framework, as part of the utopian Enlightenment–liberal project to rewrite morality and law based on a principle or set of principles that can be attained rationally and in the abstract.
Second, these theories should nonetheless be known to extract some recurrences in the functions of rights, as well as to recognize their partial validity. There are indeed occasions in which a “will” is made into a right, such as marriages, contracts, and as the name suggests, wills. And there are also circumstances under which basic human “interests” are rendered into rights in the same way, e.g. the human need to eat translates into the right to food. This sober and limited theorizing can probably find its place. Interestingly, when societies that did not typically resort to Western-like conceptions of rights translated Western legal concepts into their languages, they fittingly recognized such plurality, as did the Chinese in speaking of “power, authority, interest.” 14 A right can indeed be one or the other, or even be found at the border between the two – as it is difficult to distinguish nature from culture, it is sometimes unclear what is a “need” and what an “interest.” Yet to rewrite the function of rights by restricting the focus on a principle such as “power,” “authority,” “will,” or “interest,” when exclusively conceived, will turn out to be impossible or misleading.
Thus, we have seen that, with rights, the form is unitary and systematic – the Hohfeldian scheme – and the function is pluralistic and diverse. In reviewing the origins of the idea of rights, the politics of their justification, and continuing the search for their essence, the controversial, refractory, elusive nature of rights is bound to become increasingly apparent.
2.1.3 The Origin of Rights
Rights occupy such a central role in today's morality and politics that it might be surprising to discover they are relatively recent as a concept. Unlike main and general ideas of law, morality, and politics, such as justice, good, and evil, and despite being now considered inextricably linked to these – a violation of a right is often considered a mere synonym of a breach of justice – the term and the concept was not employed, at least not in the modern sense, by societies such as ancient Greece and Rome, nor is it geographically universal even nowadays. There have been, there are, and there could yet emerge, worlds without rights. Granted, this does not mean that these societies were and are “rightless” in the sense of being immoral. If the ancient Greeks believed that refusing hospitality to a needy stranger was “against the gods,” “against nature,” or “against reason,” that was as strong a reason to provide help as speaking of a “right to seek asylum.” 15
And yet, the very contingency of the notion of a “right” does not weaken its importance because rights characterize our society and its morality and politics in a way that reveals something distinctive of them.
There is some agreement in dating the birth of the concept of rights to the beginning of modernity, the Renaissance, or the late Middle Ages. During the first period, the term was used to point to the obligations of natural, religious, and canon law, as exemplified by the systems of Aquinas and Suárez. With Grotius, Pufendorf, and their contemporaries, the idea of rights is gradually detached from theism, religion, and faith, and the argument is advanced that, even if atheists were correct, the constraints of moral law would still be accessible to rational inquiry. The famous expression by which Grotius epitomizes this concept is etsi Deus non daretur (meaning: “even if God did not exist”). 16
John Locke, another prominent theorist of rights in modern history, established in this way the preeminence of rights to life, liberty, and property, without any implication on the nature of a summum bonum, or “highest good.”
The age of the revolutions endowed with political and legal efficacy what until then were mostly advanced philosophical innovations. It is in this period that the rights vindicated were more and more frequently considered “human,” for example in the French Declaration of the Rights of Man (1789). The turning points in the history of Anglophone countries, such as the great rebellions and revolutions in 17th-century England and the American Declaration of Independence in 1776, all have central roles in the history of the development of this concept. Arguably, they started with the 1215 Magna Charta Libertatum (“Great Charter of Liberties”), which limited the power of the English king and established the liberties and immunities of the subjects.
From the secularization, the politicization, and democratization of “rights” stemmed also their large expansion to the civil, economic, social, and political realms. These became the goals of the protests, revolts, and movements of the 19th and 20th centuries. The full development of modern nation-states, in particular with the adoption of ideologies of romantic origins in the 19th century, deeply impacted rights and citizenship. The status of citizenship with its rights and duties was then tightly linked to history, culture, ethnic origin, and political allegiance. In the meanwhile, a science-like bureaucracy was gradually put in charge of interpreting and applying rights. The entire system of Western bourgeoise nation-states came to a culmination and at the same time to a crisis with colonialism and the ultra-nationalism that fueled the world wars.
With the United Nations Universal Declaration (UD) in 1948 and the two Covenants of 1966 the history of rights touched its apex: an almost universally agreed-on list of moral precepts was finalized and became publicly known all around the globe. These developments also stimulated debates and processes with a focus on measurement, implementation, and enforcement. Several decades after the Declarations and Protocols, their legacies are normatively paramount, but their practical import has been disputed. 17
Feasibility, good faith, and implementation are not the only problems for this sort of documents, as will be expounded upon in the next section. Other issues are the lexical ordering, harmonization, and interpretation of the rights they contain. The list of rights issued in 1948 is composed of 30 articles, reaching from such different matters as the entitlement to rest and leisure (Art. 24) and to health (Art. 25) to the right to take part in government (Art. 21). Yet such heterogeneous lists also go without any overarching principle to order their normative injunctions. Even more importantly, and contrary to national laws and constitutions, the interpretive and enforcing bodies of such declarations are usually underspecified, if anything at all is mentioned about them. The vagueness of such enunciations is especially evident about contentious issues, for instance, when different states and communities argue over the definition of “family” everyone has a right to (Art. 16). And generally, no indication is given as to what Hohfeldian incidents is denoted by a right, which opens up the space to argue about whether the right to health or to work and the like do in fact demand government intervention or are mere liberties the government should not infringe upon.
And as we generally welcome the extension of rights to such vast spheres as the environment or the animal realm, philosophers like Norberto Bobbio have denounced the risks that, in a context marked by difficulties in theorizing, as well as by massive and even ordinary violations of some of the most basic and uncontroversial human rights, this extension of rights risks translating into inflation of rights. 18
2.1.4 The Justification of Rights
In February 1947, under the leadership of former US First Lady Eleanor Roosevelt, Pen-Chun Chang, and Charles Malik started working on a draft for the “International Bill of Human Rights.” 19 The UN Secretariat then assigned responsibility for coordinating a preliminary draft to John Humphrey, and further to representatives from Australia, China, Chile, France, Lebanon, the US, the UK, and the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics.
UNESCO was one of the most active international bodies to join that enterprise, by assembling committees and surveying leading thinkers from Mohandas Gandhi to Aldous Huxley. 20 It should be remembered that the members of the UN were then a fraction of today's, and as apparent from the list of representatives, the committee was pretty much dominated by Western thought. Even some of the spokespersons for the Global South were in reality much Westernized: the Lebanese Charles Malik, for instance, was a Christian who held relatively traditional views, and Pen-Chun Chang, the Chinese representative, came from Taiwan – continental China not being represented at the UN back then – and later taught at the University of Chicago before passing away at his house in New Jersey. Nonetheless, as Western thought is by itself very pluralistic, finding convergences should have proven difficult. The fact that it was less such than expected is epitomized in an oft-quoted laconic sentence by the French Thomist philosopher Jacques Maritain: “We agree about the rights but on condition no one asks us why.” 21 In this view, Maritain displays an optimism about the merging of the traditional and the modern, of the partisan and the transversal, that resisted unshaken at least until his last book. 22
This statement expresses as explicitly as possible the interpretation of “rights” that is accepted here. Rights are seen, descriptively, but also understood, theoretically, as “normative intersections” (intersections between normative systems that are then abstracted from these latter): as a content of the “overlapping consensus” that was later to be defended in the work of the great political theorist John Rawls. Rights can be part of any traditional social system, including a collectivist one, as long as there is an individualist impulse, and there are practical necessities regarding the regulation of the relationship between the individual and the collective. Thus, the possible birth of the concept of rights in the debates among orders of Franciscan monks – as to whether any property should be allowed, for example, and within which limits – is illustrative. 23 Yet rights in their most interesting forms – rights treated as freestanding and autonomous or even primary entities of sorts – arise as a necessity when a plurality of social and moral systems interact or clash. For the practical needs of living together – under religious civil wars, in diverse societies, in international organizations and diplomacy – arises then the need for moral and legal parlance that is able to abstract individual normative injunctions from any given worldview or broad and controversial system of justification. In this function of minimizers of conflicts, rights and the accompanying ideologies are necessarily opaque, ambiguous, ambivalent: any specification that is not strictly necessary to signal and strengthen agreement must be postponed to further debate, to the court, to a decision by the law of the stronger or, if the disagreement does not threaten civil order, to perpetual confusion and no decision at all. 24
The liberal–modern constitutions are all examples, to varying degrees, of how such a doctrine and practice can justify itself, and work: they are, at the same time, a display of its limitations. Indeed, as there is no possibility of synthesizing the basic systems – socialism and liberalism, say, or Protestantism and Catholicism, or the combination of these four with additional doctrines such as in the case of Germany – the abstraction of neutral ad hoc, even à la carte moral–legal principles such as the right to life and property becomes necessary. As Ernst-Wolfgang Böckenförde explained with unique clarity:
The liberal, secularized state draws its life from presuppositions it cannot itself guarantee. This is the great risk it has made for the sake of liberty. On the one hand, as a liberal state it can only survive if the freedom it grants to its citizens is regulated from within, out of the moral substance of the individual and the homogeneity of society. On the other hand, it cannot seek to guarantee these inner regulatory forces by its own efforts – that is to say, with the instruments of legal coercion and authoritative command – without abandoning its liberalness. 25
Rights, in the sense employed in the Western, pluralistic liberal democracies of advanced modernity, correspond to this dualism. They are abstracted from their cultural substrate into the neutral institution of the state. But they cannot survive or be justified on their own. In order to be filled with normative force, or just be defined specifically enough to warrant implementation, they need to be seen through the lenses of this or that specific political theory – academic philosophies have propounded a variety of them, often without securing agreement broad enough to make them socially relevant – of this or that political ideology – environmentalism, say, or nationalism – of this or that religion or comprehensive worldview – such as Islam or Marxism.
Rights are therefore unsaturated, abstracted normative injunctions presented in a neutral form. They presuppose or even require interpretations and enforcement by external agencies. They are not self-motivating or self-justified or freestanding.
The constitutions and, more loosely, the political and legal arrangements of the modern age generally reflect the underlying social and ideological pluralism: the fight between Catholicism, Anglicanism, and increasingly other Protestant and less conformist doctrines in Great Britain; the emancipation of the Jews, religious tolerance, and a substrate of theism in the case of the French Revolution; a broad variety of conceptions to be protected by the First Amendment in the US. It is, however, in the constitutions that are born out of the Second World War, and with internationalism and a significant amount of social diversity in mind, that this “overlapping consensus” and its corresponding corpus of rights as normative intersections are apparent. In that age, a specific spectrum of ideologies – those explicitly and most closely corresponding to Nazi-Fascism – was eliminated: not through philosophical debate, but through military annihilation. Correspondingly, an international consensus was to emerge and, over time, constrain and eventually disqualify remnants such as racial discrimination in the US and the apartheid regime in South Africa.
Let us consider briefly a document that is coeval to the UD: the Constitution of Italy, which came into force in the same year, on January 1, 1948. At the time the constituent, assembly was composed of several opponents of the previous Fascist regime. Between them, we find figures as diverse, if not opposed, as Alcide De Gaspari, leader of the Catholic Christian Democratic party, and Palmiro Togliatti, the Communist politician whose close connections to the Soviets led these latter to name a Russian city after him. At the time, for an orthodox Catholic, the endorsement of Communism was a ground for excommunication while for orthodox communists, Catholic beliefs were a reactionary ideology and the “opium of the people.” In principle, it would not be exaggerated to wonder what rights, if any, could have been agreed upon coming from such distant ends of the ideological gamut. Despite these deep clefts, the Constitution was drafted, and rights that so peculiarly marked the political culture of Italy like the social protection of the workers were recognized and enforced by both sides. In general, the Constitution and the rights it enunciates are examples of overlaps (and compromises) between ideologies as diverse as political Catholicism, communism, socialism, liberalism, republicanism, etc (Fig. 2.1).
The convergence on the democratic character of the republic, on popular sovereignty, on the right to work, and its central importance in the construction of the political community, all give place to divergences as soon as the rights derived therefrom are detailed, applied, or even interpreted.
A much more complex and broad overlap is obtained between and among the ideologies, worldviews, and cultures that came together for the drafting of the UN UD of 1948. The differences between such a global perspective and the case of a nation-state like Italy are, on the one hand, the increased diversity and distance between the ideological and cultural components, and on the other, the absence of a political body to regulate the main aspects of the life of a people. The UN UD simply provides a general orientation in addition to already developed national institutions, and to orient them. Yet the challenge and possibility of articulating an agreed-upon set of “rights” remain the same.
In other words, the hermeneutic suggestion is simply to take rights at face value: as the outcomes of encounters, confrontations, and negotiations between otherwise disparate if not irreconcilable doctrines. Such compromises are not justified or legitimized by definition, but merely as pragmatic agreements aimed at finding a peaceful coexistence. They are functions of the broader normative landscape, and interpreting them independently would be as difficult as interpreting the fluctuation of the stock market independently from the economic, social, and political variables that are reflected in it.
The political and ideological convenience of an appeal to rights is therefore especially evident under conditions of pluralism and democracy, where consensus – even if broad or based upon misunderstandings – opens the doors to power.
The empirically testable counterpart to this account is some degree of tension between “rights” and any systematic moral philosophy are by definition irreducibly in tension. Any attempt at reworking a normative system “the other way round,” that is to say, by starting from rights as departing blocks and arriving at general principles, would run the risk of being obliterated by contemporary changes in the very set of rights that are considered. 26 More radically, rights that are meant to work as compromises cease to make sense when considered independently: in the previous example of the democratic republic of Italy, a moderate right to strike would have been eliminated by both a conservative, social Catholic understanding of the relations of production and a radical communist theory of class struggle. Yet while no right to strike at all would make more sense from one perspective and an unlimited right to strike – or to revolution – from the other, a moderate right to strike is perfectly understandable as a workable compromise.
This understanding is therefore admittedly vague. 27 Rights, like versatile bricks and sticks, find someplace in many kinds of constructions. In fact, very few philosophies or political ideologies argued that depriving people of their livelihood and of a fair and reliable judiciary are fundamental principles of justice: those who did so, like Nazi-Fascism, have been wiped away from the table of history, and it is by no accident that only after they were the attempt at articulating international law and morality received a renewed impulse. 28 Counter-intuitive doctrines that cannot reserve even a small place for rights to life, freedom, basic bodily well-being, etc., however expressed and phrased, are doomed to disappear in a sort of “natural selection of ideas” or of their proponents. Such doctrines ought of course to be resisted: contrary to Jonathan Quong, the reply to Nazism does not need to be a bullet. 29 Indeed, most of the time – in education, for instance – we do not reply to Nazis by shooting. The theoretical point is very simple: it is easy to show how Nazism is self-contradictory and unsustainable: based on logic, common sense, any scientifically and factually informed conception of human nature, or the main system of thoughts that enjoys the respect of humanity. But the practical aggressiveness of such ideologies makes the advancing of theoretical points often naïve and irrelevant, and at times even counterproductive. After all, a good argument can be coupled with a good bullet when strictly needed. 30
It is philosophically more interesting to consider (1) the rejections of conceptions of rights and (2) more radical rejections of normativity in and by itself, such as nihilism (or radical skepticism).
2.1.5 The Rejection of Rights
21st century readers from Western countries might be surprised to know that the very concept of rights has been radically criticized: and not necessarily by extreme or fringe thinkers, but by leading philosophers, including some writing in the tradition of the Enlightenment. As each of these critiques is extremely complex, and for the present argument there is no need to delve into any details, we will not consider them closely. Interested readers can refer to the sources directly. Here, it will suffice to recall the main points and show that these disparate writers display in fact a certain convergence.
Jeremy Bentham, the founding father of utilitarianism, took issue with one of the earliest declarations of rights: the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen. In his powerful text Anarchical Fallacies, Bentham shows that the list of rights cannot be interpreted literally and that it offers a fragmented, piecemeal view of normativity. 31 Although Bentham is a writer of the Enlightenment and he shares the rationalistic, humanistic, and democratic assumptions of the Declaration, he considers such a list of rights devoid of any unifying principle to be more problematic than advantageous to moral and legal progress. It is possible to conceive of some form of reconciliation between Bentham's utilitarianism and a list of rights: for instance, in some version of “rule utilitarianism.” However, his monistic focus on the sole principle of utility forced Bentham to argue against the project.
A counterpart to Bentham's critique is the surprisingly converging thesis by the conservative English thinker Edmund Burke. Of course, Burke's problem was not that rights should be ordered and harmonized through reference to a unifying principle such as “utility.” On the contrary, to Burke, any such unification sounded worse than simplistic and utopian. In the Reflections on the Revolution in France, he makes it clear that he prefers his “rights of an Englishman” to the rights of “man and citizen” simpliciter. It is only through the complexities of history and culture that the general principles of natural law – whose classical conception Burke draws directly from Cicero – can be realistically and reasonably implemented. Rights are meaningless and dangerous without these: without institutions, precedents, prejudices, and wisdom, such as assemblies, courts (both royal and judicial), pulpits, debates, police forces, communities, families, history, and traditions.
Very distant from Burke, a second authority in the progressive tradition that rejects the very concept of rights is Karl Marx. In The Jewish Question, Marx rejects the thesis of those who support formal emancipation for the Jews, arguing that substantial discrimination and alienation will not be alleviated by the removal of their legal counterparts. More generally, here and in the rest of his philosophy, Marx considers the idea of subjective rights to be part of the ideology of individualism and capitalism: indeed, the quintessential right, which serves as a model for all rights, is the right to property. It is perhaps the most famous and central claim of Marx's philosophy that private property is a form of alienation. Marx rejects rights on a deeper level than Bentham: for Bentham, rights are, as he says, fallacies. They are logically inconsistent and linguistically vague and misleading: the plane of Bentham's critique is logic and the philosophy of language, even if, at the level of principle, his systematic views of normativity are incompatible with the fragmented repository of the Declaration. For Marx, rights are the manifestation of an erroneous anthropology: one in which human beings are narcissistically focused on their possessions – “I have a right to this and that…” – rather than on their social nature and interdependence.
A much more radical and, to a certain extent, qualitatively different critique is articulated by Friedrich Nietzsche. In the works of his maturity, and clearly in the Thus Spoke Zarathustra, Nietzsche exposes the emptiness of Western normativity, revolving around an idea of God that was by then already outdated. Modern individuals must now reckon with the heroic task of a “revaluation of all values.” Duties and rights are now based not on I ought, but on I will. Science, progress, religion[…] All the guiding principles of Western civilization have been deprived of their mystic sacredness – in a Twilight of the Idols, and have become, in and by themselves, unable to sustain individual and social behavior. 32
Nietzsche's impassioned rebuttal was to return in the form of scientific detachment and analytic rigor in the writings of Axel Anders Theodor Hägerström, and the school of “realists” that drew from him. Hägerström surveyed as large a sample of Greek and Roman laws as materially possible in his search for “the essence of all law.” 33 The result he found was that all law has no essence at all. Hägerström could only recognize, in his characteristic sobriety, that rights as social facts present themselves as “actual forces, which exist quite apart from our natural powers; forces which belong to another world than that of nature, and which legislation or other forms of lawgiving merely liberate.” In other words, right and duty would amount to superstitions. The reviewers who complained because his monumental study of legal antiquities prevented Hägerström from spelling out his normative theory more fully seem not to appreciate the implications of such discovery in full.
A number of contemporary philosophers have built upon these critiques or added their own and sometimes both.
Alasdair's MacIntyre skepticism about rights has three main sources. MacIntyre's initial philosophical position was that of (analytical) Marxism, and he appropriated the rejection of liberal individualist anthropology and its normative implications that we have seen in Marx. Later in his career, and as his rejection of post-Enlightenment morality and politics evolved, MacIntyre rejected belief in rights as the like of a belief “in witches and unicorns.” The terminology is similar to Hägerström, and MacIntyre draws extensively from the Nietzschean and postmodernist “tradition” to argue that all the Enlightenment's attempts to provide an independent justification for morality have failed. Yet MacIntyre does not embrace Nietzsche's nihilistic and super/post-humanistic perspectives. On the contrary, MacIntyre considers Nietzsche's life and theory as largely a reductio ad absurdum. 34 The superhuman is unachievable and the individual who sets out to the “revaluation of all values” is bound to become uncomprehensible and prisoner to the loneliness and burden of the feat. 35 If the Enlightenment project of a new foundation of morals based on rationalistic, ahistorical, universalistic premises fails and the very dissolution of that project in Nietzschean and postmodern thought is unlivable and offers no constructive alternative, what is the way out?
For MacIntyre, this consists of a return to the classical – Aristotelian and Thomist – the(le)ological view of human nature. MacIntyre references philosophy of science to argue that the most workable theory, however imperfect and flawed, is to be preferred.
A colleague of MacIntyre's takes a very different route. For Raymond Geuss, “no solace” is to be found in discredited, outdated theories from the Ancient and Middle Ages. 36 The rejection of the moralistic and unsubstantiated stance of normative ideologies can only issue in the mystic transcendence of A World Without Why. Similarly to Ludwig Wittgenstein, for Geuss the ethical is to be found in experience and existence. At the same time, Geuss discards the political theory that harkens back to Rawls as based on unargued “intuitions,” and the corresponding parlance of rights as relying ultimately on assertion (poignant criticism of flat assertion was already found in Bentham). 37
Two other contemporary critiques merit a brief mention. The former is Michael Ignatieff's denunciation of human rights as “politics and idolatry.” 38 Far from arguing for their rejection, Ignatieff points out that the fetichism about (human rights), as exemplified by treating them as unquestionably authoritative and self-explanatory principles, is detrimental to the culture of rights itself. On a very distant political position, the conservative philosopher Mary Ann Glendon accepts rights but criticizes “rights talk” as too subjective, too self-centered, and too focused – as opposed to duties – on the receiving, passive end. 39
2.1.6 A Critical Redefinition of Universal Rights: Validity and Limits
In order to proceed in spite of all the difficulties raised thus far, these objections need to be considered and, ideally, answered. In a sense, I will do so, and in another sense, I will not.
First, it should be noticed that these critiques are of three very different kinds. Jeremy Bentham and Karl Marx reject the language of rights, but they do propose an ethical–political source and organizing principle themselves: utilitarianism and communism respectively. As anticipated, the parlance of rights is especially foreign to, and at tension with, such standpoints, but it is not necessarily incompatible with them. Once it is established that a certain action maximizes utility, it is not entirely inappropriate to say that someone or everyone has a “right” that this or that action be performed; once the individualistic and subjective premises of capitalism are rejected, it still makes sense to declare that “the working class has a right to the collective ownership of the means of production.” MacIntyre's critique is similar: he draws from classic Aristotelian–Thomism to defend normative positions that could easily be translated into the terminology of rights, with some correctives. The problem emphasized by MacIntyre is especially that of recognizing rights' derivative and atomistic nature. For him, rights can make sense only as part of larger embodied narratives – that is, of practices – which give them definite limits and temper them with duties. Even a minimal, “soft” form of Burkeanism could be accommodated to such more distant theories: all these doctrines require a tradition and a community to function. Therefore, while the communitarianism and traditionalism of Burke are certainly to be rejected by Marx, MacIntyre, and Bentham, a more moderate form that is displaced from the center of morality and is turned into a mere corollary of the respective doctrines seems to be more compatible with them.
Glendon and Ignatieff can be accommodated more easily: their problem is not to “unplug” rights from their liberal–universalistic justificatory source – even if Glendon would be sympathetic to such a move to some extent. They rather intend to correct the linguistic and social dangers of an unchecked language of rights. Glendon raises awareness of the risks involved in “rights talks,” while Ignatieff advises against attributing to (human) rights a quasi-magic or religious power, or even a life of their own.
Yet all these theorists focus, in a way, on rights as the “shell” of normativity: as the form that is inadequate or incapable of expressing certain normative principles (utilitarianism, Marxism, Aristotelianism[…]) which they found to be correct.
Critiques of the Nietzschean kind are, of course, most difficult to address. And in a sense, I will not even attempt to do so. There is no dearth of updated reflections on the “sources of normativity.” 40 Yet a substantial engagement with Nietzsche's nihilistic Prometheism, or Hägerström's scientific positivism – which practically amounts to a form of skepticism or normative indifference – is beyond the needs and scope of this work. It is sufficient to believe that some moral system is plausibly capable of resisting their objections. Their critiques prove fatal to rights and laws that are isolated from their sources: but without delving into the debate, it is not unreasonable to assume that some replies – possibly more than one – to their biting objections can successfully vindicate the coherence and effectiveness of a normative system.
Thus, perhaps surprisingly, I do not reject these critiques of rights but rather build on them. While there has been no space to consider these systems in detail as they would deserve, I would consider the core of their rejection of rights to be one and the same. I hope to have sufficiently explained why the rejection of rights does not, by any means, coincide with immorality or amorality. When the Native Americans condemned violence against family members as contrary to their customs, to nature, to the will of the spirits, to the common good, or on any other such grounds, they were acting just as morally as the 21st century New Yorker who orders not to violate the right to bodily integrity of this or that person. The former resorted to an entirely different moral language that corresponded to just as different a worldview: but the moral substance is equivalent.
Thus, the theory of rights that I am offering assumes a different underpinning depending on the underlying theory that is plugged into it. But what is then its utility? Is such a position tantamount to radical relativism? Even at this broad and abstract level, the answer is at least twofold.
First, the theory should suffice to understand the meaning, implications, and limitations of debates and clashes over rights. It has therefore a hermeneutic–interpretive–explanatory function.
Second, the theory conceptualizes rights as a lingua franca, a neutral language that can be employed for intercultural communication and dialogue between different normative systems and worldviews, especially with a view to identifying possible overlaps and compromises. The theory adds information about the limits to such lingua franca. As it has been explained, it is precisely those overlaps and compromises that are then granted the status of rights, even if I hold that projecting a life of their own on them could be misleading and practically problematic.
It is evident that rights thus understood cannot claim the centrality they are often granted in political debates and processes: they are neither freestanding nor invariably ultimate. I will later suggest complementing them with another normative incident that remains central in non-Western normative theories and ideologies and was more central to traditional Western normative thought as well: duties. 41 Yet even this addition does not solve all problems. Rights, duties, or a system that comprehends both still do not provide a workable moral (or legal) system.
Bentham is right: no coherent whole can be built on such fragmented, diverse, vague, general, and potentially conflicting injunctions (a “right to life,” a “duty to help,” a “right to self-defense,” a “duty of non-interference”). At least not if taken exclusively. And Burke is right: it is not only abstract principles of the kind of Bentham's utilitarianism that can weave these fragments into a coherent whole: one needs at the very least historical experiences, institutions, and the shared life of a community for them to find their place and meaning. From a socio-political point of view, Burke is also generally right in stressing the importance of tradition, “prejudice” (in the sense he gives to the word), and conformism to strengthen normativity, even if the positive lights he casts on these phenomena call for qualification, and to be beneficial they need to be coupled with the exercise of critical reasoning at the individual and collective level.
Marx is, I believe, right in claiming that the anthropology of liberal individualism is insufficient to ground normativity. 42 I also concur with his thesis that the language of rights, when employed acritically and without correctives, can have confusing and even alienating effects. 43 The extent to which this risks happening depends, however, on how individual subjective rights are arranged and importantly on how they are temperated with responsibilities and duties. 44
MacIntyre is right that only from within a specific tradition and practice one can meaningfully understand and engage with any given theory and view of rights. It is, if not impossible, at least highly implausible to rebuild morality and law “upside down,” so to speak: namely, by starting from rights cleansed of their sociocultural–historical–practical origins and backtracking toward some integrated neutral conception to replace their “partial” sources. A “view from nowhere,” if only were it possible to obtain, would not guide some specific person in their search for just as specific somewhere: a “view from nowhere” leads nowhere. MacIntyre then offers a useful example of an attempt at complementing the parlance of rights with normative sources that integrate it: by his specific return to the Aristotelian-Thomist tradition, and by his general emphasis on traditions, narratives, and practices. The former will inevitably leave many dissatisfied: many will prefer Confucianism, Hinduism, Marxism, or some form of Enlightenment system (as MacIntyre notices), liberalism itself has turned into a tradition. But the latter is, I would believe, less problematic: most if not all Confucians, Marxists, and many liberals would recognize the central normative role of individual and collective histories and experiences (narratives), of their established modes of inquiry (traditions) and of their playing out empirically and experimentally in the pursuit of this or that good (practices).
Nietzsche is also right that, at least in some contexts, there is a socio-ideological crisis that has deprived many if not all traditionally endorsed normative injunctions of their authoritativeness and effectiveness: not only “God is dead” for a large share of the world's population, but so is “progress,” “reason” and many other surrogates that the Enlightenment introduced in its place. As I have claimed, however, neither Nietzsche with his followers have been able to offer a workable alternative to ground individual and, especially, associated life beyond their destructive critique, nor should it be assumed on principle that Nietzsche's genealogical deconstruction works the same with every and each (post-)Enlightenment normative system, with scientific projects explaining normativity such as evolutionary psychology and sociobiology, with the traditional Aristotelian-Thomist framework, with Marxism, with all the world's religions and non-theistic systems like Buddhism alike, and so on. Some people will continue to find Nietzsche convincing purely and simply, and by this, they will inevitably find themselves beyond right (and wrong). But others, both individuals and societies, will find in this or that version of the theories and worldviews I have just mentioned, in some combination of them, or in some development or interpretation of them, or in some other kind of normative sources I have not considered or of their own making, a reason to reject Nietzschean nihilism and to fill the parlance of rights with motivational and normative content.
Correspondingly, Hägerström's search for the essence of the law could well end with the finding that the law has no essence: because the essence of the law came (comes) from outside of the law itself. The Greek-Roman systems that he explored, for instance, offer a formidable conceptual and institutional machinery, but ultimately fail to make sense when abstracted from the concrete social conditions and the ideological worldviews that were associated with them.
While Geuss, as mentioned, is closer to Nietzsche than to MacIntyre in his rejection of such systematic strategies to solve the crisis of normativity, there are elements in his view that are to be accommodated. His critical understanding of rights is common to others: his analysis of the historical and institutional roots of a rights-based normativity is just as valid. 45 Finally, his “mystic” realization that normativity, and evaluation, cannot claim the entirety of, or even the centrality in human existence can complement this theoretical understanding most fittingly.
The final two criticisms are easiest to accommodate. Glendon's denunciation of the corrosiveness and groundlessness of “rights talks,” with the implication that this would contribute to social disintegration, is consistent with the account I am here offering. Indeed, the interpretation of rights I have sketched, and its being historically and sociologically informed, is meant as a partial corrective.
The same can be claimed with regard to Ignatieff. While rights should not be simplistically reduced to politics and ideology, politics and ideology do play a crucial role in making rights emerge, and the very existence of the language and concept of rights has been explained above as a result of politics and ideology among other factors. Therefore, even when talking about rights (and duties), as I will continue to do here, fetishizing these – “idolatry,” as Ignatieff calls it – should be avoided.
The democratic ethos and institutions, based on votes and the formation of majorities, lead to the value of the broad appeal of general and abstract formulations.
The ideological history of Western societies, and others, in particular those characterized by Abrahamitic religions, lead to attribute a transformative power to “the Word,” to the point of creating realities – as in the beginning of Genesis – or of constraining human behavior – as in the case of the Ten Commandments.
Individualism, philosophical and practical – for instance as dictated by the conditions of production of post-industrial societies – induces to privileging subjective “rights” that can be vindicated as a safeguard of an individual's interests and freedoms without any intrinsic and explicit link to this or that collective, organization, or ideology: “[R]ights language […] presumes moral individualism and is nonsensical outside that assumption.” 46
The pluralism inherent in Western liberal democracies has led to focusing on the “overlapping consensus” between comprehensive doctrines, and to justifying and legitimizing politics based on this restricted common reference only.
While a more comprehensive analysis would be possible, these four factors explain much of the centrality and role of rights in the contemporary moral and legal language, especially in the West.
Yet the power of deliberation is limited. It is one thing to win over support for one policy: it is quite another to implement it. And as Fascism and other forms of demagoguery have shown, popular appeal and support do not automatically translate into moral and rational legitimacy. The same holds for rights (and duties) that are democratically established.
The power of “speech” in general – “rights talks” or others – is also limited. Once a right or a duty is sanctioned, it often takes at the very least education and understanding, and at most surveillance and coercion through force, to have them realized. This education and understanding, and these surveillance and coercion require in turn a culture and a way of living, together with a social and institutional apparatus. There is little hope of converting this world's “villains” simply by preaching “rights” to them, and there is no direct causal relationship between identifying and proclaiming a “right” and the real world being bettered or otherwise altered by this finding and proclamation. 47
The power of individual-based right claims, while cherished by the culture and institutions of liberalism, can contribute to their success within these: yet, even in liberal societies, resources are not magically multiplied by the corresponding multiplication (inflation) of rights claims, and rights accorded to one may well translate into rights being taken from another, even if in a way that is indirect and not immediately evident. Also, the continuous strengthening of individualism does not automatically translate into empowerment: it can also contribute to anomie – the concept sociologists employ to refer to the breakdown of shared social values. Once that one is used to articulate one's demands in the neutral, abstract, subjective form of “I have a right to x,” one is also increasingly dishabituated to justify the same claims in terms of collective interests, histories, and ideologies, or even in more neutrally pragmatic terms. The risk is that of ending up as prisoners of “rights echo chambers,” where the validation of one right rather than the other can only appear as arbitrary to any outsider, given the abandonment of normative languages and theories that are more encompassing and normatively deep. Rights individualism can end in rights solipsism. This is indeed a risk with the sort of atomization and polarization of political discourse we witness in the West.
Finally, pluralism and diversity are not achieved as a fait accompli, once and for all, and with their invaluable assets come a number of challenges. As Black Lives Matter, “culture wars,” and other sociopolitical struggles in Europe and the US show us, even rights that were sanctioned to accommodate a broad range of identities and standpoints “neutrally” from the very beginning do occasionally become obsolete and untenable and, especially under conditions of material scarcity, there is no guarantee that a normative culture primarily focused on abstract rights (and duties) will suffice to support social cohesion in the long run. After all, such a culture where rights are normative centerpieces, rather than the appendage of broader normative theories and ideologies, is progressively taking shape as an unprecedented experiment. Its decisive emergence after the Second World War and with the cultural revolutions of the 1960s and 1970s does not afford enough data to predict its trajectory beyond a few generations.
As mentioned, rights are often complemented by other normative incidents (or relationships), such as responsibilities and, more classically, duties: fundamental, individual rights can therefore be linked to collective fundamental duties. 48 , 49
Before proceeding with a working list, let us resume, rephrase, and expand some definitions:
A right: we use the word “right” to mean an obligation proposed by one or more normative system(s) that is widely accepted and/or institutionalized in our pluralistic society and is abstracted from its original and partisan (as opposed to “neutral”) source(s). 50
Fundamental rights:
the rights that are presupposed by all the other rights.
the rights more widely recognized and fully supported in a particular society at a certain time.
the rights actually accepted as fundamental in our society. 51
So when we say “This starving child has a right to be fed,” we make an assertion that is equally open to interpretation as a way to “ease someone's unnecessary pain,” in the utilitarian system, as obeying the imperative to behave according to a law that could be rationally universalized, in a Kantian form of deontologism, or as the Muslim, Christian and Hebrew theological precept to “feed the hungry poor,” and so on. All this while avoiding the divisions that would arise in case we drew on a peculiar “comprehensive doctrine”: divisions that will reappear as we try to specify further this right, the way it must be enforced, its (lack of) priority over my freedom to spend my money in resources according to my own needs and choices, etc. The moral attention is so switched from the subject, the duty-holder, to the right-holder, the one who is “benefited.” As a consequence, the duties connected to rights, and the very recognition of rights themselves, sound impersonal: there is a right somewhere there, independently from my opinions, actions, or omissions. 52
The practical simplicity of the proclamation of an atomistic right consists in its allowing us to abstract from any broader normative system. Consider a trivial example: someone jumps me in the queue at the checkout counter and I shout: “She does not have the right to do it!” This apparently unproblematic situation is morally complex and there is no universal doctrine or formula that can tell me a priori if my claim can be vindicated. Is the woman pregnant? Is she coming back after having exchanged a flawed item? Is her obligation to queue moral, in the sense that is merely based on the normative relationship between us; ethical, in the sense that it is regulated by a customary or written code in this and/or other supermarkets; legal, if potentially regulated by law: or all the three of them, or none? There are, normally, some conventions, some customs, some traditions, even some prejudices, or some procedures, that influence what we take to be (a) “right” in this as well as in more complex situations. These include emergency waivers and appeals for revisions of hitherto unchallenged precedents. Yet in a large if not majoritarian set of cases, nothing needs to be spelled out, or even considered consciously.
This example shows that everyday rights can also be found at the humble intersection between habits and moral precepts or beliefs, or between different habits only. Usually, we see our customs as “rights” only when they are under attack; when some unusual individual or collective situation calls our presuppositions into question; or when we encounter disagreements and anarchy. No declaration included the liberty to breathe, even though there certainly is such a liberty, and air pollution might turn it into something worth spelling out. 53 By and large, dramatic moral/political normative reflections and debates tend to occur at moments of individual and collective crises. Adolescence serves as an example of when the individual transition between groups and statuses is accompanied by an evolution of morals: at the collective level, a civil war over the institution of slavery exemplifies a typical kind of crisis. Morals and rights become problematic when different civilizations meet also, as with the Greeks and the Asians at the beginning of the history of philosophy: e.g in the Third Book of Herodotus' Histories the Callatiae encounter the Greeks and display attitudes toward cannibalism and the burial of their deads. Finally, there are internal, ideological transformations of mentality, that it is difficult to reduce to corresponding social changes, such as when the British society secularizes and the crime of blasphemy is correspondingly abolished.
2.1.7 A Provisional List of Fundamental Rights and Duties
Let us now compile a list of basic rights and duties I will use as a basis for a theory of global citizenship, and as a touchstone to verify the legitimacy of national citizenship. It is only a working blueprint based on the Declaration of 1948, a core model for ethics and politics.
This document has been selected for many reasons. It proclaims rights: on the contrary to the Covenants, it is more oriented to defining principles than to pragmatic enforcement, in line with the present inquiry into general normative theory; it is concise, considering in 30 articles only many of the central moral and political issues of our times; it is internationally, even if not universally, accepted since it attracted a stable and large agreement. Instruments that have been developed in response to it, such as the 1990 Cairo Declaration on Human Rights in Islam and the 2004 Arab Charter on Human Rights, are possibly compatible with it, and translatable into it, at least on some interpretations. 54 Here is a workable summary:
According to the Declaration, all our societies recognize:
A duty to promote every human being's bodily and mental integrity, to provide them with drinking, food, clothes, space, housing, health care, free time, rest, leisure, reasonable freedom of movement, and protection from illness, menace, torture, mutilation, aggression, detention within moral limits, and no other limits (Articles 2, 5, 9, 12, 14, 16, 17, 19, 22, 23, 24, 25).
A duty to institute, enforce, defend, and eventually reform or substitute a judiciary and the means needed to protect fairly and to strengthen every human being's rights and duties and to fairly compensate for their violation within moral limits and no other limits (Articles 6, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12, 14, 15, 16, 19, 20, 22, 23).
A duty to institute, enforce, defend, and eventually reform or substitute global and local political institutions observing and strengthening fairly these duties and the corresponding rights, within moral limits and no other limits (15, 21, 22, 23, 28). 57
A duty to, at most, participate in, at least not to disrupt, and possibly, contribute to establishing a social and cultural life that includes schools, families, associations, and trade unions, favoring art and science, and similar “higher” activities within moral limits and no other limits (Articles 16, 19, 20, 26, 27). 58
This stipulatory yet central list calls for five clarifications.
To begin with, the first duty implies all the articles of the Declaration. In the dignity of the human being, we find the whole and complete set of rights that his or her “reason and conscience” can recognize and observe. 59 This very right, the “right to have rights” (and to have duties, and much more) is the fundamental right that translates into global citizenship (see next chapter). Arguably, all the rights and duties stem from an onto-bio-psychological foundation: that is, a possible attempt to circumvent the disagreements from which rights have been “extracted” would be by agreeing on a minimal, shared philosophical anthropology. However, this task would require much more work than the swift “philosophical diplomacy” that led to the drafting of the UD, and its outcome is not as guaranteed.
Second, as argued, a large part of normativity is not captured by rights or duties (or responsibilities, or the like). Individual and social benefits, as emphasized by all utilitarian theories, are here invisible. Also, duties and rights, even if sanctioned by (inter)national institutions, begin with one's own private environment and lived experience, as in a sort of expanding circle. Therefore, existentialism and virtue ethics have also captured other aspects of normativity. Also, by defending one's bodily integrity, for example, by not polluting our common environment, or when promoting culture and education, one gains in turn a safer place to live in and a more stimulating community. As Martin Luther King powerfully argued: “Injustice anywhere is a threat to justice everywhere. We are caught in an inescapable network of mutuality, tied in a single garment of destiny. Whatever affects one directly, affects all indirectly.” There is a complex web of individual and common goods that gives point and purpose to rights and duties: but no “declaration” or list will ever suffice to capture it. In this context, rights and duties can be conceptualized as different features, perhaps opposite ends, of a single normative structure: by abiding by my duty to respect others' rights I also defend my own. 60
Third, a number of important, even fundamental issues are conspicuously absent from the UD. For instance, it presupposes sovereignty, and it says little to nothing to clarify how a system of sovereign states is to be organized in practice. As we will see, I consider this the typical example of how rights (and duties) need to be contextualized into, and complemented by, a real-world narrative with all its details, in order to become understandable.
Fourth, and relatedly, this scheme is open to a variety of readings. Where are religious freedom and freedom of expression to be placed, for instance? If rights and duties imply and support each other, one is to choose whether religion should fit into the first rank, in consideration of the spiritual dimension of human life and understanding dignity as a special relationship of humans to God – as in Islamic or Christian readings – or if it should be located among cultural rights and duties, as a humanist would more probably prefer. The same can be said of freedom of expression: if it stems from human rationality, as for example in Kant's thought, one cannot constrain it without directly offending human dignity. 61 Otherwise, it could also be considered to be indirectly protected by the fair judiciary (see the third set of duties) or to pertain to the freedoms necessary to the development of a good body politic (the fourth duty) or even, in some contexts, to that of art and science (the fifth). The majority of universal, general rights, though, like those mentioned in Article 16, are accomplished only if many different duties are observed: for example, family, which gives an important contribution to most people's bodily and physical health, to education, etc., is also “entitled to protection by society and the State.” Namely, it should be recognized and defended by a fair judiciary and a well-ordered political system and so with all the complex intertwining of social and political life. These five main areas of duties and rights (1 – human dignity; 2 – bodily and mental integrity; 3 – the legal/moral sphere with its evaluative presuppositions; 4 – the institutional domain; 5 – the domain of “the civil”: society and culture) are strictly interrelated as well.
Fifthly, while proclaiming rights can sound liberating, reminding duties can sound enslaving. How is one to live their life while oppressed by such demanding norms? A traditional distinction taken from Western moral philosophy proves useful: it is articulated in Thomas Aquinas' Summa Theologiae (II, II, Question 40, Article 1) and it has been adopted by his followers, including some forefathers of international law (for instance, in Francisco Suárez De Legibus). 62 There are, if any, only a few negative duties that hold always and in each case: do not kill innocents, etc. The majority of moral, even legal injunctions are to be realized conditionally: e.g. you “heal the sick” only if you work as a nurse, or when caring for your close ones. These precepts still hold always – they are generally valid – but not in each case. One does not need to feel compelled to enter a hospital and work whenever one sees one. The right (possibly even the duty, dictated by self-respect) to rest, leisure, and distraction, finds its proper place in this scheme of things.
2.1.8 Human Rights and Human Nature
Is the perspective I am offering boundlessly relativistic? 63 As stated, the purpose here is not directly that of working out an underpinning for (universal and fundamental rights). It is instead that of helping understand rights, and elucidating constraints that any justification will face, either in its construction or in its expression. However, before turning to other issues about the “right to have rights” and the dialectic of rights, I would like to provide a sketch – and nothing more than a sketch – of a way to establish such an underpinning in relation to human nature.
There is, in fact, a large number of simple, undisputable truths rights can be built upon. To quote Iris Marion Young's argument against child labor and exploitation: “Exhaustion and the need to use the bathroom are cross-cultural experiences.” 64 At the macro level, and in the long run, economic and social stability in a society that would not recognize or grant any right to workers would be doomed to collapse quickly. And the same holds with regard to many other human, fundamental rights, such as rights to life, a minimum of liberty, etc. While only comparative sociology and history can vindicate this argument, it seems at least worth considering in principle.
In the classic tradition of natural rights, divine law and the rationality of the created universe encompassed and sustained moral precepts. But in a much thinner sense, human rights are “natural” in the sense that they are shared by everybody simply by virtue of their humanity. 65 This is the “liberal” conception of “natural rights” or “natural duties,” as formulated for example in A Theory of Justice. 66
Some contemporaries have advanced other views of “natural” human rights, grounded in contemporary biology. Noam Chomsky, in a debate with Michel Foucault, suggested that one urgent task to be undertaken “is to try to create the vision of a future just society; that is to create, if you like, a humanistic social theory that is based, if possible, on some firm and humane concept of the human essence or human nature” (emphasis added). 67
More recently Steven Pinker has again explored the implications of neuroscience for political and moral thought: the foundations of his views are nearly the same as Chomsky's, but the conclusions they draw are opposite, as one is a liberal, and the other a radical thinker. 68 In particular, Pinker challenges “the blank slate prejudice” which would affect modern philosophy at all levels – epistemological, normative, and so on. Linguistics provides some ground for theorizing a universal structure of human reasoning in that it has traced syntactic elements that are mirrored in neural circuits, and present themselves identically – or in a fixed set of variations – across all human societies and languages. If this linguistic homogeneity corresponds to a broader bio-neural–behavioral convergence, “human nature,” namely a scientific account of culturally invariant features such as genes, the structure of the brains and bodies, and the like, would deserve attention by moral and political theorists, and potentially play a role in debating universal values, principles, and norms of conduct. 69 Even the Chomskyan scholars who focus prevalently on linguistics have noticed that principles such as “recursion” (namely the unique property of human languages, that makes it possible to combine a potentially illimited set of sentences) point to a unique relationship between human nature, infinity, and freedom. 70 More pragmatically, Pinker analyzes the results of comparative ethnography to conclude that many other relevant “cultural universal” exist besides grammatical rules embedded in the physiology of the human brain. 71 The “human universals” he cites from Donald E. Brown include items ranging from “conflicts, consultation to deal with” to “division of labor by age” (Donald E. Brown, “Human Universals,” arranged in alphabetical order by The Daily Omnivore: https://thedailyomnivore.net/2014/08/21/human-universals/). 72
Even supposing that it is possible in the first place, it is not easy to draw moral conclusions from such a list of anthropological facts. Tacking care of the sick is a human universal, but so is stealing and warfare: yet moral judgment about these could not be more diverging. Without a systematic approach, such as through a scientifically informed philosophical anthropology, it is only possible to single out “certain features of our common humanity,” or non-relative “spheres of experience,” as Martha Nussbaum calls them. 73
Still, this impressive bulk of commonalities shows at least that there are some grounds for suspecting and establishing the existence of an identifiable human nature. A successful attempt at deducting some moral implications may or may not follow: a look at the history of humanity, including the history of thought and global philosophies intent in articulating such that, yields at best mixed and resistible results. The mere existence of a “human nature” is a necessary condition to give legitimacy to this naturalistic view, but it is controversial whether it would also be sufficient. Chomsky, Pinker, and in a very different way also Nussbaum, though, have some strong arguments and facts on their side: since Book Eight of Aristotle's Nichomachean Ethics, indeed, it has been noticed that “Even when traveling abroad one can observe that a natural affinity and friendship exist between man and man universally.” 74
The experience of moral disagreement is also very common, and travelers can be struck by both: Herodotus' classic passage on cannibalism, already cited above, serves as a counterpart to Aristotle's quote. It is therefore easy to share in Rousseau's “surprise and disgust” while inquiring about the disproportionate divisions between those who believe in a natural law: indeed, a very narrow group of philosophers (and a much less significant number of people). And any attempt at specifying the content of human rights, and applying them, has indeed proved almost as divisive. 75 , 76 Nonetheless, this bookish confusion should not lead astray, nor should we welcome with excessive indulgence Rousseau's case against the consistency of moral and legal systems that successfully sustained civilization for millennia. Yes the customs of the peoples are disparate: but there is no country in the world where killing, stealing, lying, and raping are the norm rather than the exception. Whenever there is a written or oral normative code, these actions are generally and clearly forbidden, and this has been so for the vast majority of history. This is at least an invitation to hope that, in practice, an “overlapping consensus” or equivalent compromises about moral issues could be found, and that in theory, it should be possible to vindicate and ground it into a conception of human nature.
2.2 The Right to Have Rights
To the extent that the purpose of the rule of law is to achieve some sort of shared liberty, the achievement of nondomination means that all must have some kind of status, if any are to have it. If that is the case, then this status cannot be derived from or acquired with some specific membership, say in a political community.
–James Bohman 77
2.2.1 Human Rights, Human Dignity, and the Global Polity
The classic foundation for human rights is dignity. This latter term has been criticized for its vagueness, but it finds a place in most philosophical discourses. Essentially, it has to do with what a human is worthy of (dignus, in Latin). 78 The question that is classically central in the domain of justice is what is owed to each person: to give “everyone one's due,” as stated by a phrase variously employed by Cicero, Ulpian, and Justinian in the early days of Western jurisprudence. Its key component is the relevance and distinctiveness of being human, of what is owed to humanity as such. Human dignity so understood relates to the inherent value of personhood, its intrinsic moral relevance, which entitles one to a particular consideration as a member of a community spanning as widely as humankind. While much thinner and less politically organized than a nation-state in its explicit and enforced obligations, such a community would nonetheless be morally and ontologically preeminent. If one has human dignity, one possesses human rights, and the right to have rights that precede them and is presupposed by them.
In this context, dignity can be presented as “the right to have rights.” 79 Hannah Arendt's formulation of this most fundamental right refers to the implied existence of a global polity since this right is not predicated on any specific particular political community. 80 Humans being “political animals,” a person cannot fully exercise her rights if not as a member of an organized society. Many important articles of the Universal Declaration, such as Article One, which mentions dignity explicitly, and Article Six (“Everyone has a right to recognition everywhere as a person before the law”), are highly compatible with this idea of a non-disposable right to be respected as a human being at every relevant level (moral, legal, political).
The two occurrences of the term “right” in this formula have two different meanings: the first “right” lacks a particular addressee since “humanity as such” is, at present, something much more fluid than any nation-state. The paradox is that what appears to be morally more significant is hardly definable, while the apparatus that distinguishes between citizens and “others,” and whose legitimacy is open to question, is well-identified and materially more forceful. Even nowadays, rights declared by international documents are not enforceable if not through national agencies: the extreme case of the controversial “responsibility to protect (R2P)” notoriously requires in practice that some state acts “on behalf of humanity.” The most fundamental right is therefore very different and much less practically relevant than ordinary rights, and still needs to find its place in “a specific juridico-civil community of consociates who stand in a relation of reciprocal duty to one another.” 81
2.2.2 Cosmopolitan Norms From Global Violations
The global polity, the One World evoked in Arendt's analysis, is a matter of fact, a historical situation, rather than a political institution. 82 Arendt herself considers the modern nation-state the only purveyor of rights and the only context wherein the exercise of those rights is possible. 83 At the same time, though, the arbitrariness of the extension or limitation of membership, the wavering distinctions between subjects and strangers, are incompatible with a universal justification of rights. In this way the situation described by Arendt appears as a “paradox,” a contradiction between the requirements of the respect for universal rights and the internal limits of political institutions. Even the “civic” criterion of membership she endorses is potentially exclusionary. Arendt also knows that nation-states are not to be considered a given, since they undergo frequent and radical transformations, or are even created anew. 84 She refuses the idea of a universal state sovereign as starkly as Kant. However, the possibilities of political evolution transcend the dualist alternative between central global governance and contemporary nation-states. Arendt's “experimental, fluid, and open reflections on how to constitute democratically sovereign communities, which did not follow the model of the nation-state, were not explored further,” but they brilliantly alluded to a reality similar to the present. 85
Indeed, as Benhabib claims, we have entered the era of “cosmopolitan norms of justice.” This peculiar cosmopolitanism does not consist of a visionary utopia but is rooted in the conditions of global politics. The period in which states negotiated as the only legitimate agencies, the era of “international norms of justice,” ended when states themselves became capable of losing their legitimacy in the eyes of citizens, especially if unfairly denaturalized. As citizens can be made non-citizens, a state may become a non-state. Of course, both of these incidents still occur in cases of emergency. Nowadays even democracy is limited by international norms and institutions. 86 Legitimacy has become a global question.
A “crime against humanity” is not the same of a crime against humanness: the former is a crime against all human beings, against the very existence of humanity itself. 87 A genocide is a criminal act against a whole community (since it is perpetrated against a whole ethnicity or nation) and by virtue of that, it is set at a very different level than the murder of an innocent within a state. 88 This latter is to be judged according to the state's laws. But the universal relevance of genocide elevates it to a global arena: states must be coherent with the concept and comprehended in the physical extension of humanity, therefore humanity embraces and surpasses all and each political community. By attacking the entire Jewish people, Eichmann exceeded the jurisdiction of the German state, and as a consequence was legitimately judged on very different bases than those regulating its national context only. 89 Eichmann's trial is an example of a trial in which humanity faced an individual who violated the “right to have rights”: in other words, a trial where humanity confronted an individual who denied it. 90
2.2.3 Humanity as an Agency
The problem posed by the recognition of a “right to have rights” (or the identification, creation, and distribution of a basic status to which rights apply) is not the same as a violation of an individual right. 91 When a person is not treated as such, despite being apparently given all the consideration that is due to a human being, her rights are seen as the benevolent and dangerously contingent concession by a domineer. Thanks to the creation of the international human rights regime, this issue has become a practical question rather than a philosophical one. Still, the international rights regime does not specify agencies and means sufficient to enforce human rights, and the identification of these instruments is an urgent matter of philosophical, moral, and political reflection. 92 Collective actions and even an evolution of present institutions are needed to answer Arendt's plea for humanity to care for and decide on what affects humanity.
The otherwise legitimate distinction between citizens' and non-citizens’ rights does not apply to human rights, as acknowledged even by those who argue for distinguishing such rights when it comes to distributive justice: I think here of Thomas Nagel, Andrea Sangiovanni, and Michael Blake. 93 One of the problems with these accounts is that they do not emphasize the continuity between human rights and the socio-economic dimension. In any case, a “citizenship gap” is affecting the stateless and displaced together with the citizens who, without a sufficiently harmonic cooperation of states and a more relevant international authority, are affected by the effects of globalization. 94
2.2.4 Coercion and the Requirements of Reciprocity
Coercion, reciprocity, and participation in processes of autonomous deliberations generally make the bonds between citizens much tighter. This has been mentioned in arguments to justify international economic inequalities, as well as other such as cultural and the like. The question posed by Arendt, however, regards the justification of citizenship as a guarantee of human rights, its limits, and its compatibility with global duties. 95 It evokes, if not invokes, the possibility of a global polity, that emerged from the intertwining of human destinies made visible by the last centuries' historical developments and catastrophes. And, coupling this to the “right to have rights,” it implies some form of global citizenship. A number of critical points should help reassessing this set of issues.
First, the acceptance of a minimal respect for human rights is taken as a given. 96 The enforcement of the human rights regime is considered a practical difficulty. Yet usually, theorists do not even list human rights in detail, which would already be somewhat controversial. 97 There is disagreement over the precision and legitimacy of many Articles of the UD already, such as those regarding socioeconomic rights. How could the present world order be sufficient to the enforcement of human rights, if there is no clarity about what counts as a human right? And since there is neither a hierarchy of rights nor a definition or quantification of human rights violations that are “tolerable,” these theories potentially expose every state to punishment if not outright aggression. Also, who should prevail between sovereign states and organizations like the UN and a single sovereign state? The “global justice theorists” have not fully spelled out their take on this respect. A coherent theory of combined (or clashing) sovereignties is, at least at present, missing, and it has been substituted by anarchical and chaotic practices. 98 De facto, the “burden” of defending human rights weighs principally on the nation-state. As long as the cooperation of the international community is dysfunctional, and its legitimacy is open to question, we will lack a workable philosophical and theoretical understanding of how human rights are to be understood, interpreted, assessed, measured, and enforced. 99 , 100
Second, and relatedly, political institutions are also taken as a given. 101 This approach appears less naive than a utopian philosophy, which freely dreams about global polities as if nation-states had disappeared. “Global justice theorists” would rather accept the present world order, even when they advance requests for significant changes. This realism is to be welcomed. Consistently with it, one can notice that some important institutions defy the polar opposition “global-local (national).” 102 The EU is obviously the first example that comes to mind, but one can wonder whether federal states are not already situated beyond the protomodern, monolithic concept of sovereignty. Even strongly unitary states sometimes defy dualism between the national and international: for example, China's “Special Economic” and “Free Trade” zones. 103 States change and adapt seamlessly: it has always been so in history, and there is no reason to think that in the era of globalization, they will cease to do so. Rather, the relationships with outsiders and between states will adapt accordingly.
However, and as a third point, the most blatant examples of “blurring” between national and international are to be found at the individual, rather than institutional, levels. Migrants live more or less stably in between countries and this affects both the respect of their human rights and their equal status, whether based on their contributions as quasi-citizens or not. 104 They take part in the hosting state's social and economic life, and they are exposed to state coercion, but often, their status is not proportionally enhanced. Citizens of a collapsed or failed state are in a much worse situation since they can be deprived for a long time of objective-institutional counterparts to subjective citizenship, namely without any appointee to the defense of their rights apart from the feeble and often de jure guarantees from the international community. This is also the case in most extreme cases: minorities who are persecuted to the point of being dehumanized, the state of war, the concentration camp. 105 And even such cases are not after all really “marginal,” as exceptions may become the norm, wars are prolonged, and refugee and segregation crises affecting millions are protracted over decades.
The fourth and last point regards the definition of coercion presupposed by the “global justice theorists.” 106 Establishing a cut-off point to determine whether people are coerced by a state or institution or not is not at all simple in theory and is bound to be contested and controversial in practice. 107 Partly, this is a matter of economics: decisions by one state, or even by private institutions, can plunge entire populations into poverty: and it is hard to find anything more coercive than the threat of starvation. 108 Also, paradoxically, within or without international institutions, nation-states have been able to inflict more coercion – through military intervention – on foreigners than on residents. These are ordinarily presented as reactions to threats from foreign countries, such as terrorism, diseases, and massive migrations. 109 Be it as it may, there is certainly no way by which “foreign subjects” can hold their dominators accountable. Therefore, the reciprocity-coercion argument should be played the other way around: in the cases in which we clearly detect international coercion, we should demand a proportionate transnational system of enfranchisement and participation also. 110 The contradiction between universal claims of equal concern and the exclusion of outsiders is thus far from completely settled, despite the arguments of the “global justice theorists,” and the “outsiders” who live within state borders can constitute a constant reminder of pressing inequalities. 111 This is why Bohman consistently speaks of “Cosmopolitanism at home”: the justice of the whole system is diminished if this proves ineffective in addressing anyone's legitimate claims for freedom.
It follows that justice cannot be reduced to the setting of “sufficiently fair” standards of (re)distribution in the local, even less, in the global arena. 112 Justice implies also an imperative demanding the expansion and implementation of just institutions (as well as practices and procedures) operating in all the relevant fields. Rawls argued that justice compels us to abide by just laws on the one hand and to reform them and establish new ones on the other. 113 Since consent plays an important role in legitimating an institution, the “institutional-political” implication of “global justice theorists” could have conservative implications. 114 The legitimization of an institution, in fact, is not contingent if it is predicated on its commitment to justice: the alternative to a recognizably legitimate international order is a Hobbesian-like state of war. 115 , 116 In my interpretation, the impulse to enhance global institutions together with ties between individuals and the national institutions they belong to, and also to favor the recognition of humanity “at home,” is continuous and consistent with the primitive inclinations toward social and political life. The fact that we are already distributed in communities, does not eliminate the need for harmonization: a dispute between states over the control of some resources is not different from two individuals fighting but causing greater destruction. 117 In this limited sense, the “domestic analogy” between individuals and nation-states holds: states do not recognize any vertically superior power, nor do they behave like individual citizens, but conflicts between them cannot be abandoned to a Darwinian/Hobbesian fight for the dominance and survival of the fittest. 118 Poverty, attempts at genocide, crises in international relations, massive migrations, pollution, climate change, terrorism: all these can be addressed properly only beyond Westphalian sovereignty. Many accomplishments are already possible only through transnational alliances and cooperation at all levels. These need to be recognized, supported, and sustained by a cultural, social, and psychological effort for understanding, respecting, and harmonizing different civilizations and national communities. From poetry to science, to arts and sports, the achievements of our age exceed boundaries. Identities and meritorious traditions can be preserved and thrive, even more in the context of a harmonious global community. Benefits for individuals, from refugees and migrants to residents and citizens, are also enormous, and the risks of an unsafe and dysregulated international environment are too grave to be dismissed. Originally, it was impossible for human societies to survive without a common organization: this led to the setting of principles of limited range. Yet these implied, e.g., a spatially unlimited principle of non-interference. 119 Now circumstances of justice have changed and require the integration of each state in a system of “global citizenship,” as well as the reconsideration of non-citizens within the state's boundaries, of “marginal cases” and “states of exception.” And these not for reasons opposite or additional to those which led to state formation, but rather as the natural continuation of those latter. 120 Just as entrance into society was indispensable for the communal enjoyment of rights, some form of global society is now needed to cope with global and local problems coherently: as a consequence, we have a natural duty to promote it actively, a duty that cannot be misrepresented as a matter of supererogatory generosity. 121 , 122
2.3 Rightlessness as a Path Toward the Extension of Status
[T]he path from anarchy to justice must go through injustice.
Thomas Nagel. 123
As mentioned previously, history and globalization have brought the world to a condition of unprecedented connection. This factual condition, which one could call “cosmopolitism,” precedes and integrates “cosmopolitanism,” in the sense that the possibility of a global polity (polis) is a prerequisite for the existence of its citizens (polites). Nagel seems to believe that a coercive authority of sorts is likely to come into existence before the establishment of perfectly just power relations necessary to manage it. This resonates with Waldron's view that the suited institutions arise as a way to prevent injustice and as a reaction to it. 124 These institutions may be unjust to some extent too: their legitimacy depends also on their effectiveness, on popular support, and on their relative advantage over anarchy. 125 The “cunning of history” would be directing the formation of a global polity through global states of nature in which, with many accidental constraints, power legitimates itself. Irrespective of whether this is reflects the spirit of Nagel's own argument or not, I do not believe that this process should be deterministic and ideological. 126 This “dialectic” view of global development should not serve as a justificatory tale to excuse injustices. Rather, I believe the path through injustices can only be established if and when one reacts effectively to injustice.
2.3.1 Power Through Exclusion: The Paradox of Sovereignty
This lends the occasion to introduce a theoretical device both to understand that process, and to grasp better the ambiguity of the “right to have rights”: the idea of “inclusive exclusion.” According to Giorgio Agamben's theory, the space in which political power first arose is where law detaches itself from nature. 127 Since humans are naturally “political,” that is, born in an organized society and acting according to judgments instead of mere instinct, the way in which sovereignty is originally exercised is by sanctioning or lifting the “banishment.” “Banishing” consists of “abandoning” someone to the state of nature, therefore excluding the subject from the reign of law and by doing so showing her total dependence on the sovereign itself. It is through this exclusion that the inclusion in the state of subjection is made possible as a power exercised against all, a power whose limits are not visible because the subject lives within them, and trespassing them would cause death. An original “biological” world, a pre-legal state of liberty, is in modern politics unthinkable. 128 Freedom, in other words, a proper human life, comes to existence only through the polity: libertas est civitas. 129 , 130 And slavery, as Aristotle famously argued, is a condition less than humane, and is only pre-political life: outside of the city no human is found, but only gods, beasts, and “talking tools” (slaves). Still, even within the boundaries of the political life was something one could arbitrarily dispose of on some occasions, as with the Roman vitae necisque potestas. 131 Therefore the definition of the sovereign as the one “who decides on the state of exception” is consistent with Arendt's idea of a “right to have rights”: the fullness of sovereignty is not in the decision on this or that particular right, but in the definition of who is entitled to bear rights tout court. 132 Sovereignty is traditionally unquestionable because all the political questions can be posed only within its framework, on its supporting basis. It is the condition of the possibility of politics, and, since human life is essentially political, it is also the condition required for living and respecting humanity. The outsiders, beings that barely exist, were correspondingly considered almost incapable of questioning anything, all the more the sovereign power. The “political view,” which takes present institutions as a given, is therefore at a loss in considering how to opt in new members. Rather, already existing nation-states need, on this view, merely to justify their coercion, a requirement that is implemented only by the (recently acquired) democratic political agency of the people. But since such institutions, as Nagel clearly concedes, were not created for that purpose, tensions and discrepancies were to be expected from the very beginning. 133 A theory of rational sovereignty, and especially a theory of the rational evolution of sovereignty, is still needed. From this open question originates the problems of the “citizenship gap”: the global extension of rights, which is not the mere enforceability or overreaching of sovereignties. 134 Contingent political institutions, for a number of reasons, disguise themselves as “natural,” and by doing so they not only avoid the re-definition of the “social contract,” but also confirm the dangerous confusion between law and nature, illegality and non-existence. 135 , 136
If Agamben is right, in fact, something more relevant is at stake. If the “sovereign ban” is the original definition of who is included and who is excluded, a definition that by itself extends to both categories by implying that the excluded are, whether they like it or not, cut off from entitlements provided by that society (which, in practice, could mean excluded from society or life altogether), a global polity would be a very dangerous, totalitarian, and inescapable global subjection. 137 Is the idea of global governance, however imagined, to be coupled with the frightening possibility of a global state of exception, namely of the global suspension of human rights? Are we to face the difficult choice between (pre-political) non-disposable rights which are not enforceable and (political) enforceable rights which are necessarily disposable? 138 If so, it comes as no surprise that even some of the staunchest cosmopolitans are wary of the characteristics global institutions could assume. But otherwise, are rights always to be defined and restricted by a limited community, as Burke's “rights of Englishmen” illustrate? And which “third way” could be found out of this dilemma, if traditional sovereignty posited itself as monist and unprincipled, a mere fact to be questioned and justified only after its establishment and acceptance? 139
Nagel's realistic insight on this suggests that we can expect a regime of global injustice to consolidate before global justice becomes possible. But since this is no self-unfolding cosmological principle, and we are not assured of the extent of this injustice, nor of our own survival, it is reasonable to elicit as much resistance as possible as soon as we notice its symptoms. Political regimes often present themselves as natural and, if some form of the theory of natural duty is correct, we can take their point: even if no individual political institution is really so indispensable, the existence of some institution is necessary and required by the universal “right to have rights,” namely by humanity itself. 140 But as the birth, the evolution, and even the dissolution of nation-states have revealed historically, a possibility of directing the process according to some requirements and ideals coexists with this necessity. The shape cosmopolitans give to their global polity is very indistinct, but so were other ideas advanced in the past while debating the constitutions of the states we see at present. In single, situated cases of rights violation, we can discern some paths toward the evolution of citizenship. There is no reason why one should wait until injustice has ripened to establish a more just global community. We do not need total injustice to move from anarchy to justice. We can proceed through facing limited problems, and then try to harmonize the institutions needed for their resolution. The characteristics of global justice are to be worked out as an answer to specific, contextual violations of justice and undue coercive oppressions. There is no assurance that, even in this way, necessarily just institutions will be the outcome. The sum of single improvements, each of which is positive in itself, could turn dangerous if unforeseen and difficult to control, and it could also be twisted to pursue ends that were not inherent in the process of its genesis. As it happened with the dissolution of feudal loyalties, the result can be a well-ordered, unified political entity, absolutism, or both at different times. But the perspective risks of the future do not excuse complacency with the injustices of the present – and the past. In fact, both the violation of minimal redistributive justice meant to redress dramatic deprivation and that of basic human rights undermine the credibility of institutions responsible for them. No individual, and certainly no state, should turn a blind eye toward such violations against any human being, and the discrimination of non-citizens in this respect turns out to be a challenge to state's legitimacy even in the citizens' eyes. 141 Yet, nothing in principle guarantees that a more substantial international order will promote these rights instead of greater domination, as nothing guarantees the same to the founders of any given country.
2.3.2 The Foundational Role of Outsiders
In many myths and national stories, the nation is re-founded by a foreigner who is capable of making the polity anew with his/her double nature of a revolutionary, threatening to destroy the establishment, and of a brave migrant bringing in new energies. Bonnie Honig has argued that the strangers, marginalized, and excluded bear the philosophical and political re-founding of the legitimacy of national institutions. 142 Democracy requires that all its power is grounded in the defense of people's authentic interests and freedoms, and this assumption is both challenged and verified through processes of inclusion. “Marginal” cases provide the nation-state with a test of embodied universalization: it is only through them that political principles of equality, fairness, fraternity, and universality are coherently embedded in practices. 143 In the era of globalization, non-citizens also work as tests for the nation-state to show that it is still able to perform its original instrumental function: protecting subjects from violence and injustice and coping with an environment that would prove dramatically too complex and hostile to individuals. Honig's idea of democratic cosmopolitanism does not determine a specific institutional arrangement, and she denies that either global citizenship or world government is implied by it. Since this idea relies on the particular and unpredictable demands of each practice of integration, the outcome of these trade-offs between in and outsiders will be understandable and explainable only retrospectively. 144 , 145 Yet independence or even opposition between laws and practices should not be exaggerated to the detriment of both. Laws and practices may sustain each other, and if one of the two poles becomes predominant, either fluidity is transformed into evanescence or solidity into rigidity. 146 Moreover, practices and laws must be in line with each other. The task of advancing both cannot be left on the shoulders of the oppressed, of those who most suffer for their defects: therefore, their expected roles should not be conveniently – and ideologically – exaggerated. It is, instead, a task human beings have in common by virtue of their nature and dignity.
2.3.3 Abject Cosmopolitanism: The Refugee/Stateless as the Essential Citizen
Peter Nyers' article on “abject cosmopolitanism” provides a case study and a restatement of such cases: it is however the very concept of “abject cosmopolitanism” that I find of theoretical interest. 147
The situation of refugees is, more generally speaking, rich in insights into the essence of citizenship for many reasons. The most obvious and not negligible, despite not being central to the argument here, is that refugees make up a great proportion of displaced, stateless people, and constitute an urgent political problem playing a significant role in international politics and diplomacy. 148 Its dimensions and dramatic intensity make it impossible to ignore. This introduces the second, and philosophically more relevant, point: refugees embody the clash of sovereignties I referred to as an issue of (meta)political legitimization. 149 They are members of a community not although but rather because they are rejected by another. 150 And therefore, as a third and crucial point, they already embody the sense and the provisions of global (or fundamental-essential) citizenship and, in my view, also of citizenship itself. 151 In its deepest meaning, the meaning that probably came historically and conceptually first, citizenship is primarily the entitlement to human rights that fades if those rights are violated, and that must be conceded by any legitimate community capable of doing so, under penalty of losing legitimacy before its members' eyes, and before outsiders. The community itself might work as a local instantiation of humanity (in loco civitatis: in the place of humanity, as David Owen has it) corresponding to universal standards of morality and rationality. 152 Refugees lack human rights (legally), they deserve human rights; they lack citizenship, they deserve citizenship. Conversely, a community provides its members with human rights, and if it does not, it is not a legitimate, “decent” community anymore: depending on the scale of these violations, it can even be considered a tyranny to be overthrown. Ordinarily, however, the right to decide whether this threshold of injustice has been crossed or not lies with a country's own people, and with them exclusively. Otherwise, it is regulated by articles 24, 25, and 51 of the Charter of the United Nations, and implemented through the general provisions of Chapter VII of the same, so that armed interventions are restricted to actions authorized by the Security Council to preserve international peace and security, while states keep their right to self-defense. More recently, in 2005, (A/RES/60/1) “Heads of State and Government affirmed their responsibility to protect their own populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes against humanity.”
The right of asylum is, just like these international obligations and Francis Deng's innovative conception of “sovereignty as responsibility,” a constitutive part necessary to global citizenship: but if we have, as I think we have, collective duties to ensure that every human being enjoys rights proportionate to his/her dignity, much more is required. 153 It may be necessary that states constitute a supranational community capable of dealing with problems of this sort. 154 And also through this means, states should study and realize policies for the betterment of the human rights regime worldwide: this would be properly a matter of foreign policy, that does not necessarily imply abuses of military interventions, even in case crises loom. Rather, international cooperation to enhance human rights worldwide is both compatible with national sovereignty and reinforces it.
Finally, there is a conception of “abject cosmopolitanism” that goes beyond the meaning initially attributed to the phrase by Nyers: “abject cosmopolitanism” is realized whenever states, peoples, and communities that have been forced at the bottom of the global hierarchy struggle to realize a freer, equal, just international order. In this line, countries and peoples who strive against colonialism and discrimination have all provided examples of “cosmopolitanism from below.”
2.3.4 Peace and the Teleology of Citizenship
On the very contrary, in Europe, where centuries of history disproved the illusion of fixing diplomatic issues through aggression, the human rights of citizens grew both within and without member nation-states thanks to the increase of economic, cultural, and personal ties, the improvement of mobility, the porosity of borders, disarmament, dismantling of colonial empires, and protection of a large number of citizens of any ethnicity and orientation through modern welfare-states. 155 , 156 These and many other technical-material improvements were coupled with a number of cultural and educational achievements, which are not as easy to list, but were no less effective in securing human rights at home and abroad: for example, the dismissal of racial and social-Darwinist discourses, and the cultural openness toward the “foreign” that increased over decades. Sure, progress is still required, and all these achievements might end up in peril at one point or another. But three aspects of the development of the EU are here interesting to focus on. 157
The first is its past: the way through which the idea of a commonwealth of European nation-states emerged is exactly the one theorized by Nagel. Wars, oppressive and unfair treaties, and even the threat of a unified imperial tyranny helped recognize the mutual responsibilities, the strict bonds, and the possibilities of convergence between old enemies and disloyal allies. The second is its present shape: a supranational regime that, despite many, undeniable shortcomings, has persuaded members to agree on common standards and destiny with regard to fundamental matters. And this, without abolishing, perhaps even without diminishing national identities. The most relevant, though, is its possible future development: the telos of the EU was peace, that is to say, the free enjoyment of rights, and the strengthening of friendship among peoples who are different yet capable of being united. It is in opposition to the catastrophic effects of war that the process of European interaction started, and solely in the perspective of the attainment of peace, not only for its members but for the whole world, it could remain a relevant experiment and a model for international institutions. In Immanuel Kant's international political theory, a “Federation of Free States,” and “Universal Hospitality” were joined together with “Perpetual Peace.” 158 A century and a half, and many disasters later, European politicians started thinking that obtaining peace without shared institutions and hospitality would have remained impossible. 159 But before I consider national and international peace more thoroughly as the end toward which the instrument of citizenship could be oriented and the idea against which each local citizenship has to be measured, I have to turn to consider, in general, the flexible functions and the essence of citizenship itself. 160 , 161
Nonsense upon Stilts (Routledge Revivals) Bentham, Burke and Marx on the Rights of Man. Edited By Jeremy Waldron (London: Routledge, 1987).
Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 2007).
The “Tebbit Test” briefly recalled by David Miller. (2008). “Immigrants, Nations and Citizenship.” The Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(4), 372 would have cheered the English team into a requirement for the candidates to citizenship, and Samuel P. Huntington cites the fact that Mexican-American booed the US soccer team as a symptom of their threatening the national identity (Huntington. “The Hispanic Challenge.” Foreign Policy, March/April, 2004, p. 37). More recently, see the debates around “taking the knee” at the intersection between sport, civil rights, and national identities.
Leif Wenar, “Rights”, in Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/rights/.
Wesley Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions, Cook, W. (ed.) (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919). My description of the Hohfeldian incidents relies primarily on Leif Wenar. (2005). “The Nature of Rights.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33, 223–253. The author specifies that his version is slightly different from the original scheme proposed by Hohfeld.
Y stands for a category of right, such as “legal” (the primary object of Hohfeld's account), “moral,” “epistemic” and so on. In this work, I deal prevalently with moral and legal rights. I also stress that the different dimensions are often linked, and that sometimes the boundaries between the one and the other are blurred. For instance, human rights are considered by some not to be rights in the strictly legal sense.
Privilege(/liberty)-rights usually exist in the “protective perimeter” of claim-rights (Herbert L. A. Hart, Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 171). The logical definition of privilege does not imply any accompanying claim or correlated duty, but a political theory deals with something more than mere logic. According to Hart, liberty-rights are appropriately understood as “rights” only when their exercise is protected (ibid., p. 173). Only in a world like Thomas Hobbes's state of nature we can imagine “entirely naked” liberty-rights, but again, this represents “little more than a logical possibility”: “In society as we know it, liberty-rights are usually associated with “protective” claim rights,” and so with correlated duties. See Peter Jones, Rights (Macmillan: London, 1994), p. 20. Thus the liberty-right to breathe (lack of a duty not to breathe) is accompanied by the negative claim right not to be chocked (A has a right not to be chocked by B); the liberty right to free expression is paralleled by the negative claim-right not to be coercively silenced, etc.
“Political Theory on Refugees,” organized by the Netzwerk Flüchtlingsforschung in Augsburg on November 17–18, 2016. I have advanced the same point in my doctoral thesis: The Migrant Crisis and Philosophy of Migration: Reality, Realism, Ethics (2018), which is to appear as a monograph. In its currently available version, the claim opens the Introduction, at page 7: https://air.unimi.it/handle/2434/589308 (last accessed on 27/12/2023).
The metaphor is taken from H. L. A. Hart, Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 183.
Event those who support the interest theory acknowledge that “there are cases in which rights and benefits appear not to be conjoined” (Jones, Rights, p. 30, my italics). It would be impossible to reconstruct the debate among interest theorists at length here: see Jones, especially pp. 26–36.
“Will theorists and interest theorists have erred in adopting analyses framed to favor their commitments in normative theory. This has turned the debate between them into a proxy for the debate between Kantianism and welfarism. Yet this normative dispute cannot be resolved through a conceptual analysis of rights.” Wenar, “The Nature of Rights,” cited pp. 223–224.
The thesis I defended at the University of Pavia under the same title in 2014.
Frydrych, D. “The Theories of Rights Debate.” Jurisprudence, 9(3), 566–588. https://doi.org/10.1080/20403313.2018.1451028; “The Case Against the Theories of Rights.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 40(2), 320–346 (2020).
As mentioned in Danilo Zolo; Globalisation: An Overview, ECPR, Colchester 2007. Confront also with J. An and J. Sun. (September 22, 2022). “Translation Strategy of Legal Terms With Chinese Characteristics in Civil Code of the People's Republic of China Based on Skopos Theory.” PLoS One, 17(9), e0273944. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0273944. PMID: 36136970; PMCID: PMC9498954; Thomas-Walters, L. (2021). “The Complexities of Translating Legal Terms: Understanding Fa (法) and the Chinese Concept of Law.” Melbourne Asia Review, 6. https://doi.org/10.37839/mar2652-550x6.18; Matulewska, A. (2019). “Legal and LSP Linguistics and Translation: Asian Languages' Perspectives.” International Journal for the Semiotics of Law – Revue Internationale De Sémiotique Juridique, 32(1), 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-019-09602-x; Mannoni, M. (2019). Hefa Quanyi: “More than a Problem of Translation. Linguistic Evidence of Lawfully Limited Rights in China.” International Journal for the Semiotics of Law-Revue internationale de Sémiotique juridique, 32, 29–46. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-018-9554-0.
See Raymond Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2008), pp. 60–70; cfr. also Geuss, Reality and Its Dreams (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2016). Geuss's historical account is in turn based on Peter Garnsey, Thinking about Property: From Antiquity to the Age of Revolution (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008).
The concept, although in a slightly different phrasing, is included in De jure belli ac pacis (The Law of War and Peace), Grotius, 1625.
It is contentious that the development of human rights declarations and even treaties has bettered lives for human beings. See Jan Eckel, The Ambivalence of Good: Human Rights in International Politics since the 1940s (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019); see also Oona A. Hathaway. (2002). “Do Human Rights Treaties Make a Difference?” The Yale Law Journal, 111(8), 1935–2042. JSTOR. https://doi.org/10.2307/797642. Accessed December 28, 2023.
Norberto Bobbio, The Age of Rights (New Jersey: Wiley, 1996).
Mary Ann Glendon, A World Made New: Eleanor Roosvelt and the UD of Human Rights (New York: Random House, 2001), p. 77.
A less optimistic tone is found in Jacques Maritain, The Peasant of the Garonne, An Old Layman Questions Himself about the Present Time, trans. Michael Cuddihy and Elizabeth Hughes (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1968).
See Geuss and Garnsey quoted above.
Michael Freeden. (2005). “What Should the ‘Political’ in Political Theory Explore?” The Journal of Political Philosophy, 13, 113–134.
Ernst-Wolfgang Böckenförde, Constitutional and Political Theory: Selected Writings, Edited by Mirjam Künkler and Tine Stein (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), Vol. II, p. 45. Confront with the debate on this “dilemma” or “paradox”: Joseph Ratzinger, Jürgen Habermas, The Dialectics of Secularization: On Reason and Religion (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 2007). I have heard a similar formulation recently, by the famous IR theorist John Mearsheimer: “My basic view is that liberalism alone does not provide the necessary glue to hold society together. Liberalism is predicated on the assumption that people cannot agree about first principles: and this is why liberalism preaches tolerance. The reason you have to have tolerance to make a liberal society work is because people do not agree about important questions involving the good life. So in any liberal society you are going to have centrifugal forces that tend to pull that society apart. And the question then becomes: what provides the glue to hold the liberal society together? And nationalism is a very important glue because nationalism says that all of the people, you know, in Australia, they are part of a nation, they are part of a tribe, they have something in common, and that something should hold them together in the face of those centrifugal forces.” Interview with (Australian former Deputy Prime Minister) John Anderson, released on December 8, 2023, minute 11 and 50 seconds and following (https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=huDriv7IAa0). Compare in particular Mearsheimer's expression (“people cannot agree about first principles”) with Maritain's view (“we all agree on rights as long as we do not ask why”). Maritain's “whys” are Mearsheimer's “first principles” and pluralism on this coupled with the unanimity of regulations to be established by law is what grounds Böckenförde's paradox. I hold that while Mearsheimer's diagnosis is accurate, his solution is unhelpful. Nationalism means as many different things as there are nations in the world: his own explanation that nationalism “tells people that they have something in common” exposes the risk that nationalism could be wishful thinking or shallow or that what people do indeed have in common be irrelevant or relatively less important or even negative and problematic. Furthermore, knowing to have “something in common” does not provide any social glue in and by itself, no more than knowing to have humanity in common has taught people to get along and transcend nations.
A similar, bottom-up approach is preferred by James Griffin, On Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), p. 29. Griffin recalls and rejects top-down approaches such as the principle of utility and the Kantian categorical imperative: but these were already attempts at securing a rationalistic, neutral, independent and objective normative consensus on their own, and not the kind of complex ideological and socio-political-cultural-legal structures that historically gave rise to rights in the first place.
I do not rule out in principle that a richer philosophical account could one day win such broad consensus to become the basis for a global moral and legal system. Yet: this seems very unlikely under present conditions, and such an account would require something both thicker and thinner than contemporary theories of rights. Indeed, philosophical theories usually propound views that are much more minimal, say, of the modern natural law conception that was at the basis of international law; at the same time, such conception was admittedly underspecified, and worked by leaving a large leeway to customs and other forms of ideological and normative complementation, in a way that a rigid sanctioning of specific rights cannot do. Also, I doubt that such a conception can plausibly be derived by reversing the perspective: that is, by starting from rights abstracted from the struggles and contexts they emerged from. To the contrary, it would require, I suspect, a philosophy, and possibly an anthropology and other interdisciplinary foundations, that could only be taken from already existing inquiries. I do not engage in such task myself here, as my goal is first of all to offer an understanding of normativity as it is presently available, and as it would be a much more demanding and very different inquiry from what is possible and appropriate here.
Some normative systems can justify more or less persuasively such deprivations in some cases, or even in many cases, but very few would argue for “anti-rights” of the kind of “a right to be judged unfairly,” “a right do discrimination and arbitrary violence,” “a right to domination and subjection” etcetera. As noted, Nazi-Fascist and similar extremist regimes realized this theoretical possibility to some extent. In general, one is more often confronted with the problem of a state of exception or emergency, or with withdrawal of rights in specific and rare cases, such as incarceration. Marginal cases and exceptions can be nonetheless explained and justified in many ways, but they are not assumed as norms (that is to say, as fundamental rights). There is no society where prison is the norm and freedom is the exception: only by force, and not theoretically, could such a society be established, and it would not spread far in space or in time.
Jonathan Quong, “Introduction”, Liberalism Without Perfection (Oxford, 2010; online edn., Oxford Academic, January 1, 2011). https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199594870.003.0001. Accessed December 30, 2023. “I therefore agree with Burton Dreben when he says, ‘sometimes I am asked, when I go around speaking for Rawls, What do you say to an Adolf Hitler – The answer is [nothing]. You shoot him” See also: Burton Dreben. “On Rawls and Political Liberalism.” In Samuel Freeman (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, Cambridge Companions to Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002) 316–346.
The speech against the Nazi Neue Ordnung by Franklin Delano Roosevelt is both an empirical account and an argument, and it works especially well as an argument as it corresponds to an empirical account: “Yes, these men and their hypnotized followers call this a new order. It is not new and it is not order. For order among Nations presupposes something enduring – some system of justice under which individuals, over a long period of time, are willing to live.” https://www.presidency.ucsb.edu/documents/address-the-annual-dinner-white-house-correspondents-association.
A version of Jeremy Bentham's Anarchical Fallacies can be found in his online opera omnia, volume II: https://oll.libertyfund.org/title/bowring-the-works-of-jeremy-bentham-vol-2.
Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 2007), p. 113. According to the interpretation given by Alasdair MacIntyre, Nietzsche is to be considered the “Kamehameha II” of the Western tradition. Kamehameha II was the Hawaiian king who abolished the taboos without facing any resistance, as they were the relics of superstitions whose origins had been forgotten long before.
Ehrenzweig, Albert A. and Barna Horvath. (1954). “Review of Inquiries into the Nature of Law and Morals, by A. Hägerström, K. Olivecrona, & C. D. Broad.” The American Journal of Comparative Law, 3(1), 117. JSTOR. https://doi.org/10.2307/837139. Accessed December 30, 2023.
Alasdair MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry. Encyclopaedia, Genealogy and Tradition (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990).
Both burden and loneliness are Nietzschean themes: see for instance the burden of the doctrine of the eternal return of the identical, and the loneliness that transpires from Nietzsche's poetry (“Pine and Lightning”).
Alex Sager, “Review of Raymond Geuss, A World Without Why”, August 3, 2014, Marx and Philosophy Review of Books. https://marxandphilosophy.org.uk/reviews/7882_a-world-without-why-review-by-alex-sager/. See also Raymond Geuss, A World without Why (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2014).
Geuss, Philosophy and Real Politics, cited p. 70.
Michael Ignatieff, “Human Rights as Politics, Human Rights as Idolatry”, The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Delivered at Princeton University, April 4–7, 2000 (available online at 495-7.qxd (utah.edu)).
Mary Ann Glendon, Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse (New York: Free Press, 1991).
Roberto Redaelli and Andreas Funke (eds.) Rethinking the Sources of Normativity, special issue in Etica & Politica/Ethics & Politics, XXIII, 2021, 2.
For the cruciality of duties in world ethics: Mangesh V. Nadkarni, “Ethics in Hinduism”, in Ethics for Our Times: Essays in Gandhian Perspective (2nd edn.). (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014); Guojie Luo, “Introduction”, in Traditional Ethics and Contemporary Society of China (Berlin: Springer, 2023); Peter Harvey, An Introduction to Buddhist Ethics: Foundations, Values and Issues (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012); Ataullah Siddiqui. (1997). “Ethics in Islam: Key Concepts and Contemporary Challenges.” Journal of Moral Education, 26(4), 423–431. https://doi.org/10.1080/0305724970260403; Gyekye, Kwame, “African Ethics”, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2011 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/african-ethics/.
For a “third-way” anthropology, between liberal pessimism and communitarian optimism about human nature, see Mario De Caro and Benedetta Giovanola. (January, 2017). Social Justice, Individualism, and Cooperation: Integrating Political Philosophy and Cognitive Sciences. Teoria, 37(2), 53–63.
In Marx's view, rights were a symptom of workers' alienation and transformed every man in a “isolated monad… withdrawn behind his private interests and whims and separated from the community.” Jeremy Waldron, Nonsense Upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man (London: Methuen, 1987), p. 146.
A responsibility-centered theoretical framework is evoked in Iris Marion Young. (2004). “Responsibility and Global Labor Justice.” The Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(4), 365–388.
For the historical roots, see the already mentioned Philosophy and Real Politics, Reality and Its Dreams; A World Without Why. In his critique of Jurgen Habermas, Geuss advances most clearly his thesis that it is the electoral, liberal–democratic social context that provides the “magic” force to formulas such as rights and, in general, to debates and concepts as opposed to facts and institutions: “A Republic of Discussion”, on The Point, June 18, 2019. https://thepointmag.com/politics/a-republic-of-discussion-habermas-at-ninety/.
Michael Ignatieff, “Human Rights, Sovereignty, and Intervention”, in Owen, N. (ed.) Human Rights and Human Wrongs: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 2001 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), p. 67.
Assuming that such Manichean language of clearly distinguishable “right” and “wrong” sides is usefully applied.
“Hohfeld himself says little on this issue but, since he presents rights and duties as correlatives and since his correlatives are supposed to work both ways, he would seem to hold that for every duty there is a corresponding claim-right.” Jones, Rights, p. 26.
To the purpose of this acknowledgment of the collective dimension of morality, and of a reassessment of the balance between the private and the public sphere, I take into consideration both the communitarian and the feminist critiques. For Carol Gilligan the language of rights mirrors the rigidness and assertiveness of the masculine voice (In a Different Voice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003)). Yet hopefully by presenting the defense of rights as a collective enterprise this confrontational feature of rights talk is somehow mitigated. Rights-language is usually employed to specify the benefits due to determinate individuals: however, the very existence of citizenship as a concept illustrates how this needs translating into a collective dimension. If a “duty designed to benefit individuals only as members of an undifferentiated collectivity” fails to give rise to a right (see Jones, p. 28), are rights then sufficient to analyze the relations between citizens, or, even further, between persons who are not part of a political society and are negotiating the conditions on which they are to enter into one or form it? Some consider rights and duties to be but two sides of a single relation (for example, see Christopher Arnold, “Analyses of Right”, in Eugene Kamenka and Alice Erh-Soon Tay (eds.) Human Rights (London: Edward Arnold, 1978), pp. 74–86): my argument does not strictly require such an approach, but I would favor it. Here, it is sufficient to stress the interrelations between rights and duties, especially as regards human and citizen rights displayed in a scenario with collective agents (states, communities). A collective duty is distinguished from a universal duty by the fact that a collective duty cannot be discharged by an individual: for example, the duty to provide children with an education. This is not conceivable as a one-to-one relation, but implies a state-system or, at least, a community. Note that this distinction is not the same as the classical Kantian dichotomy between perfect and imperfect duties. For the complexities of this latter: Hope, Simon. (2023). “Perfect and Imperfect Duty: Unpacking Kant's Complex Distinction.” Kantian Review, 28(1), 63–80. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1369415422000528. A collective duty can also be universal: see above, the duties implied by the Declaration. For examples of such duties, see the next section.
By this “abstraction” I refer to the process through which an assertion that was originally part of a systematic reasoning or “comprehensive doctrine” is proposed and judged independently from it. As the coexistence of the interest theory and the will theory shows, one single entitlement can be considered a right for different reasons. In an extreme case, for no reason at all: the justification of rights that relies on their “self-evidence” implies that rights can simply be asserted. Imagine for example that a state accepts to give out to its citizens something similar to Philippe Van Parijs's “basic income.” Suppose that this state does so because the cabinet agrees on a compromise between Van Parij's and other supportive theories. Then the entitlement to a basic income is defended by the bureaucracy and sanctioned by the judiciary more or less independently from Van Parijs's theory as well as any other, by adding other “neutral” reasons and insisting on the procedural legitimacy of the law itself. Basic income has become a right in consequence of the state's authority, that in a democracy is derived from the people's sovereignty.
These three conditions constitute a possible definition of fundamental rights which is not bound to any particular theory of rights but does not rule out any of them either. In this way, they are meant to explain the incoherence and fragmentation that is to some extent recognizable not only in rights-talk, but even in important political documents. These latter, indeed, do not endorse a singular, coherent philosophical system. I do not believe that this mainly descriptive definition of rights satisfies a critical question on the justification of morality: to the contrary, rights upheld by our society are to be called into question. In this thesis my aim is neither that of elaborating a coherent morality on my own nor that of constructing another theory of rights, but rather that of analyzing the way right language is employed, paying attention to academic debate, political institutions and practices, and everyday discussions together. Within this framework, that is the present moral and political scenario accepted in its pluralism and reordered through a particular (and therefore questionable) perspective, I hope to be able to advance challenges and suggestions. But any amelioration presupposes the reconstruction and the comprehension of the background, to which these definitions could contribute, provisional and tentative as they may be. As a consequence, both this definition and that of rights as “normative intersection” corresponds more to an attempt to definition given by a dictionary (neither arbitrary nor unique) than to geometrical axioms. In this particular sense, these three definitions are distinctively sufficient to give rise to a “fundamental right” in the acceptation of political declarations. Definition (1) is the only one which is essential to the concept of a “fundamental right” and I included it in this description of the political sense of “fundamental right” because of my belief that these two meanings tend to converge in practice, due to the rationality of the political process and of the people, that is its protagonist. My view is similar to what Beitz calls “the nonpartisan or restricted conception of human rights,” but it is different in the fact that I take this as a provisional and partial understanding of human rights, an understanding which on its own would be insufficient to support my argument. This view, as Beitz remarks, displays some commonalities with Scanlon's and Rawls's. See Charles Beitz. (2001). “Human Rights as a Common Concern.” American Political Science Review, 95(2), 269–282, especially note 3.
The same happens when we speak of “a right to life,” “a right to freedom” etc. without specifying who should do what in order to secure such rights. Indeed, one of the definitions of citizenship I am advancing consists in the primary agency appointed to the enforcement of rights.
In this sense privileges/liberties are called “defensive rights”: they are usually invoked as defenses against external repression. Samuel Stoljar, An Analysis of Rights (London: Macmillan, 1984), p. 13. See Jones, Rights, p. 18.
I thank Alessadro Bussetti for having drawn my attention to these instruments in his analysis of their standing between universalism and relativism: an inquiry I cannot undertake myself here.
Duties are literally mentioned in Art. 29 (“Everyone has duties to the community in which alone the free and full development of his personality is possible,” emphasis added). In Art. 30, the close of the Declaration, duties are implied again: “Nothing in this Declaration may be interpreted as implying for any State, group or person any right to engage in any activity or to perform any act aimed at the destruction of any of the rights and freedoms set forth herein.” By coupling this article with the previous ones, we deduce that states, groups and persons not only lack the power to annul universal rights and freedoms, which would plainly contradict the Declaration, but they are also forced not to do so, they lack the liberty to kill, oppress etc. Here “they have no right to” is synonym to “they have a duty not to.” In this case, everyone would have a duty not to violate human rights: seemingly, the most reasonable interpretation of this article and of the entire Declaration. Some room is left to argue if everyone is always required to improve actively human rights: this seems implied by Article 28. According to the text of the Declaration, though, no doubt can arise on the collective commitment to such an improvement: states, societies, communities are bound to provide their members and subjects with the means to enjoy their rights and freedoms. See also Hugo Bedau's argument: “The emphasis on duties is meant to avoid leaving the defense of human rights in a vacuum, bereft of any moral significance for the specific conduct of others. But the duties are not intended to explain or generate rights: if anything, the rights are supposed to explain and generate the duties” (“International Human Rights,” in Tom Regan and Donald van de Weer (eds.) And Justice for All (Totowa, 1983), p. 297). The issue is complex and I cannot spell it out at length here. I hope it is enough to restate my leading concern: I decided to present the duties which are correlative to the rights of the Declaration because I think citizenship has essentially to do with their enforcement. In fact, the citizen is entitled with those rights, but is also accountable for their protection, if anything as a member of a citizenry.
“All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.” Art. 1; “Everyone is entitled to all the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaration, without distinction of any kind[…]” Art. 2, and again “everyone[…]everyone” in the following articles with some exceptions (for example “Men and women of full age[…]” in Art. 16, with regards to marriage. My italics). Cf. next chapter.
“Everyone is entitled to a social and international order in which the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaration can be fully realized.” Art. 28. In practice this international order probably entails international institutions, and being the rights declared equal, the UD presupposes a form of global citizenship, as I will better explain later. Cf. next chapter.
In the sense of Abraham Maslow's “pyramids,” with creativity, purpose etc. on top of basic physiological needs.
Art. 1. For a more detailed discussion of the meaning of “dignity,” see section 1.2.
This is empirically true: yet in a conception such as Kant's, that puts universalizability and consistency at its core, it might even hold logically.
This is true of any violation of fundamental rights, since I said they are grounded in human dignity. But what I am saying here is that a certain violation may also pertain more specifically to the sphere of judicial fairness etc. The question is, in other words, if these freedoms derive from human dignity or if they lie at the core of this very dignity.
This is not the only tool offered by traditional moral and political thought, and Thomism in particular, for a reflection on global citizenship. The distinction between primary and secondary precepts of the natural law is still valuable to make sense of normative pluralism and diversity and to manage it. See for instance Lawrence S. Cunningham (ed.), Intractable Disputes about the Natural Law: Alasdair MacIntyre and Critics, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (IN) 2009.
For better or worse, I think that in this respect the definition suits much of the everyday usage of the word “right.” One could argue that the definition is therefore useless. To this my answer is twofold. First, I suppose there are some constraints on this variation, which are based mostly on facts like the characteristics of human nature I am recalling here, and other constraints derived from the world as appraised by reason, reason itself, and so on. And second, the fact that a concept is variable, or a function of other concepts, does not make it necessarily useless. For instance, and to quote from Rawls' theory, an “overlapping consensus” could exist between much diverse “comprehensive doctrines.” Being a subset, its content will vary according to the sets from whose intersections it results. Consider the vector addiction in physics: the direction and magnitude of the vectors are a matter of fact, but the rule (the parallelogram rule) through which we can estimate the result is of a conceptual nature and helps us explaining existing forces and predicting their outcome. It is worth remarking that this more “empirical” and “political” definition is not incompatible with other theories of rights to discern the genuine from the apparent ones. What I am trying to set forth here is only a standpoint for understanding political rights philosophically (namely, at a level of problematization and abstraction which is hardly available while debating politically).
I. M. Young, “Responsibility and Global Justice”, p. 108.
In the “limited sense” circumscribed by Jones: “natural rights” are valid independently from any given social and legal institution, and they are possessed by humans “simply in their natural capacity as human beings.” This sense differs from the more “substantial” one, that is historically preceding, in that it does not rely on a (theo/teleological) cosmology. See the discussion in Jones, Rights, pp. 79–82.
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 1971; revised edition 1999), pp. 98 “natural duties,” also search for the many instances of “natural rights.” “The argument for the two principles of justice does not assume that the parties have particular ends, but only that they desire certain primary goods. These are things that it is rational to want whatever else one wants. Thus given human nature, wanting them is part of being rational; and while each is presumed to have some conception of the good, nothing is known about his final ends.” p. 223.
Noam Chomsky, Michel Foucault, The Chomsky-Foucault Debate On Human Nature (New York: The New Press, 2006), p. 41. Note how Chomsky's conception of “natural” rights differs from Rawls both on the ethical and metaethical level. See also my article: “Aristotelian Ethics and Darwinian Biology: Perspectives on Human Nature”, in Sante Maletta and Damiano Simoncelli (eds.) Practical Rationality and Human Difference (Mimesis International, 2023).
Michael D. Coe. “The Language Within Us.” The New York Times; James McGilvray, “Chomsky versus Pinker on Human Nature and Politics.” In: Edgley, A. (eds.) Noam Chomsky,” in Critical Explorations in Contemporary Political Thought (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-32021-6_7.
See Chomsky's definition of human nature: “I would claim then that this instinctive knowledge, if you like, this schematism that makes it possible to derive complex and intricate knowledge on the basis of very partial data, is one fundamental constituent of human nature. In this case I think a fundamental constituent because of the role that language plays, not merely in communication, but also in expression of thought and interaction between persons; and I assume that in other domains of human intelligence, in other domains of human cognition and behavior, something of the same sort must be true. Well, this collection, this mass of schematisms, innate organizing principles, which guides our social and intellectual and individual behavior, that's what I mean to refer to by the concept of human nature.” ibid., pp. 4–5 (my italics).
Andrea Moro, The Boundaries of Babel: The Brain and the Enigma of Impossible Languages (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2008).
Steven Pinker, The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature (London: The Penguin Press, 2002).
Donald E. Brown, Human Universals (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1991); see also Brown's entry for “Human Universals” in The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1999), pp. 382–384. In the outset of this latter source Brown writes that “Human universals comprise those features of culture, society, language, behavior, and psyche for which there are no known exceptions to their existence in all ethnographically or historically recorded human societies.” “Human universal” and “cultural universal” are synonyms, at least in my use (but also in the MIT entry).
Martha C. Nussbaum, “Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach”, in Martha C. Nussbaum and Amartya Sen (eds.) The Quality of Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993). In her article Nussbaum does not rely much on anthropological observations, and not at all on neurosciences or linguistics. Aristotle's quote opens Nussbaum's article.
The quote is from Harris Rackham's translation, on the online Perseus Digital Library (see Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, Harris Rackham (ed.) (Cambridge (MA)/London: Harvard University Press/Loeb Classical Library, 1926).
Jean Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses, trans. G. D. H. Cole (London: Everyman, 1913), pp. 156–157.
Jones, Rights, p. 97.
James Bohman. (August, 2009). Living Without Freedom. Cosmopolitanism at Home and the Rule of Law. Political Theory, 37(4), 539–561.
A discussion of the concept in relation to human rights is to be found in Griffin, On Human Rights, cited above, and more recently, in a conference given by Alasdair MacIntyre, who contrasted its secular, post World War II conception with classic Thomist doctrine. MacIntyre's discussion includes a critique of theories at the intersection between the two, such as personalism. Alasdair MacIntyre (De Nicola Center for Ethics and Culture). Plenary session of the 2021 Notre Dame Fall Conference. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V727AcOoogQ, last accessed 04/02/2024. Confront also with Andrea Sangiovanni, Humanity Without Dignity, Moral Equality, Respect, and Human Rights (Harvard: Harvard University Press, 2017).
While the two concepts are usually seen as related but distinct in Hannah Arendt, this is precisely the title chosen by Christopher Menke, “Dignity as the right to have rights: human dignity in Hannah Arendt”, in Düwell, M., Braarvig, J., Brownsword, R., Mieth, D. (eds.) The Cambridge Handbook of Human Dignity: Interdisciplinary Perspectives (Cambridge University Press; 2014), pp. 332–342.
“We became aware of the existence of a right to have rights […] and a right to belong to some kind of organized community, only when millions of people emerged who had lost and could not regain these rights because of the new global political situation. The trouble is that this calamity arose not from any lack of civilization, backwardness, or mere tyranny, but, on the contrary, that it could not be repaired, because there was no longer any “uncivilized” spot on earth, because whether we like it or not we have really started to live in One World. Only with a completely organized humanity could the loss of home and political status become identical with expulsion from humanity altogether.” Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1971), pp. 297–298, my italics. According to this quote, it seems that “humanity” in Arendt's vocabulary should be understood as implying both “the mankind” and the “human nature” (as the Oxford dictionary explains them: “human beings collectively” and “the state of being human”). Arendt excludes a third meaning of the word: “the quality of being humane; benevolence.” So humanity (meaning 1 “human being collectively”) is the addressee of the “right to have rights” claimed by each human being (one who possesses “the state of being human,” meaning 2). Resolving this claim-right through normative/legal relations between individuals would be complex, or impossible altogether. A life cannot be fully human unless if it is lived in a community, and the relationship between a citizen and the citizenry cannot be replaced by the contingent relations between a citizen and her fellows considered individually. It is conceivable of someone opting out of one's, and therefore acquiring an almost complete immunity against it, but it would be impossible to opt out of humanity. As human, are naturally and inescapably entitled to its protection and to its coercion, when justly imposed. The right to have rights appears to be similar to the status of a rights-bearer (echoed in the condition required by Joseph Raz: X has a right “if and only if X can have rights…”, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), p. 166.). For the republican conception, see the discussion in J. Bohman. (2009). Living Without Freedom. Cosmopolitanism at Home and the Rule of Law. Political Theory, 37(4), 539–561. In particular on the relation between Philip Pettit's “legal status” and “the right to have rights”: “For all their disagreement, Pettit and Arendt share a common presumption present in the republican tradition: that free status generally and legal status in particular derive from citizenship, from membership in a political community. But in the case of stateless persons and migrants without legal status, this presumption that legal status is derivative of civil status simply restates the problem and not the solution. We can get closer to a solution only if such legal status is unlinked from membership in a particular community for good republican reasons” (pp. 543–544).
Seyla Benhabib, The Rights of Others. Aliens, Residents and Citizens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 58. For a deeper discussion on the issue see all the second chapter “The right to have rights: Hannah Arendt on the contradictions of the nation-state.”
This historical situation reflects a moral fact: the equal concern due to every human being. But as long as humanity was divided by space and time, ancient societies lived in practice as they were separated universes. As Arendt puts it (see previous notes) “we became aware…” (emphasis added). It is not that the right to have rights came to existence thanks to globalization, but it was made clear and its requirements became inescapable due to the possibility each human being has to impact heavily, directly or indirectly, on someone else's life, even if the two live in the opposite corners of the world. Life in the atomic age has made this mutual moral belonging even more pressing.
“The right that corresponds to this loss [that of a right to belong to some kind of organized community] and that was never even mentioned among the human rights cannot be expressed in the categories of the 18th century because they presume that rights spring immediately from the “nature” of man[…]the right to have rights, or the right of every individual to belong to humanity, should be guaranteed by humanity itself. It is by no means certain whether this is possible.” Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, p. 298. Frank Michelman has noted how this “right to have rights” does not challenge the existence of national institutions: these are the most likely addressees of claims to such a right: “The notion of a right to have rights arises out of the modern-statist conditions and is equivalent to the moral claim of a refugee or other stateless person to citizenship, or at least juridical personhood, within the social confines of some law-dispensing state” (Frank Michelman. “Parsing ‘A right to Have Rights’” Constellations, 3(2) (October), 200–209, 203.
Hannah Arendt, “Zionism Reconsidered”, in Ron H. Feldman (ed.) The Jew as Pariah: Jewish Identity and Politics in the Modern Age (New York: Grove Press, 1978), pp. 131–192.
Benhabib, The Rights of Others, 64.
Benhabib, while recalling Arendt's understanding of genocide as the most specific “crime against humanity,” says: “If, however, there are crimes which can be perpetrated against humanity itself, Arendt must consider the human being not only as a being worthy of moral respect but also as having a legal status that ought to be protected by international law. The distinguishing feature of this legal status is that it would take precedence over all existing legal orders and it would bind them (Correspondence, 419).” Seyla Benhabib, Another Cosmopolitanism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), p. 19 my italics. “This legal status” refers to “the right to have rights”: it is both legal and moral, or rather represents the defining boundary that at the same time separates and connects the field of moral and legal rights, and it encompasses all the specific moral and legal systems. The text Benhabib refers to is Hannah Arendt-Karl Jaspers, Correspondence:1926–1969, ed. Lotte Kohler and Hans Saner, trans. Robert and Rita Kimber (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1992). My view on the problem is that, considered the relations that are developing between single nation-states and international institutions, we should aim at a meta-democracy, where local loyalties are not rejected but limited by the universal allegiance to the dignity and the interest of humankind. Humankind itself, though, should be entitled to political institutions that correspond appropriately to the national participatory practices. See chapter 3.
See note 76 on the distinction humanity-humanness.
A community regardless of how this is defined: what is important here is the scale of the crime (or, more generally, of the moral-legal relation). If Eichmann had been accused of the extermination of the Berliners because of their being Berliners, this would not have changed much the substance of the trial. These mass crimes perpetrated against states, communities, groups, tribes, ethnicities and so on reveal that the relevant moral-legal relation is not internal to the groups themselves but is both collective and universal. See the following note.
The fact that this very state was at that time accomplice does not alter the issue, but escalates it to an upper level. Individuals are subject to their states, but states and individuals are subject to humanity. The fact that the Jewish people was spread beyond German boundaries is also inessential: a genocide can be accomplished against a less populous ethnic group, and also against a group confined in one state, and still be a crime against humanity. It is still a crime based upon an ascribed status: it would be no different from persecute a person because she is a person.
It is crucial not to depersonalize humanity, as it were an abstraction. Humanity means: what is inherent to every person and makes her a person. In this way Eichmann was different than a pirate, whose crime is to be judged even in the absence of a territorially competent court because of mere practical reasons. The universality of Eichmann's fault is conceptual: “he is the enemy of all, and hence can be judged by all.” Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, rev. and enl. ed. (New York: Penguin Books, 1994), p. 261.
“To have a status, as Hegel remarks, is to be someone; to lack it is to be nobody, the existence of which is not even to be counted. Accordingly, the formal rule of law may not fail to provide adequate protection from powerful private and public actors; but it can fail more deeply and sometimes catastrophically when people lack even the most basic legal status,” Bohman, Living Without Freedom, p. 541. Compare with Arendt, The Origin of Totalitarianism, pp. 296–297 “Their plight [that of stateless people] is not that they are not equal before the law, but that no law exist for them.”
“[M]ost constitutional democracies already have these republican and cosmopolitan features, with respect to the right of persons… [T]here must be a set of overlapping and intersecting institutions, each with their own distinctive powers and capabilities” Bohman, p. 558.
The articles I refer to here in particular are Michael Blake. (2001). “Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30(3), 257–296; Thomas Nagel. (2005). “The Problem of Global Justice.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33(3), 113–147; Andrea Sangiovanni. (2007). “Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35(1), 3–39. Note that they do not justify all discrimination between citizens and foreigners, even in the restricted domain of distributive justice: “This [the argument about the legitimacy of two different degrees of reciprocity, that one could call a “strict” and a “loose” criterion] does not imply that we have no obligations of distributive justice at the global level, only that these are different in both form and content from those we have at the domestic.” Sangiovanni, p. 4.
Globalization and Human Rights, edited by Alison Brysk (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002).
“The European nation-state is the largest container of democracy and solidarity that has historically become possible… one needs to be skeptical about the likelihood that history could go beyond that achievement” (Claus Offe. (1998). “Homogeneity and Constitutional Democracy: Coping with Identity Conflicts through Group Rights.” Journal of Political Philosophy, 6(2), 113–141). While this exaltation of the Western nation-state should be qualified and relativized, one can agree on the historical importance and on the merits of the nation-state. I also doubt it would be either necessary or helpful to dismantle it. Still, there is no reason to consider it a definitive and insurpassable achievement, especially considering its internal evolution and that of the international institutions that flank it. I wonder whether the nation-state, which aggregated and surpassed parochial and tribal allegiances often without abolishing them completely, would not be a suitable model for the creation of an international regime compatible with its survival. According to Nagel “A subtle version of such a system has been outlined by Janos Kis in “The Unity of Mankind and the Plurality of States” (unpublished manuscript). He calls it a supranation-state regime: separate states would retain primary responsibility for just governance, but share sovereign power with international institutions with special authority defined functionally and not territorially, with respect to trade, the environment, human rights, and so forth.” “The Problem of Global Justice”, p. 119. I believe there are better and alternative models to this “vertical” conception for instance, in the age of multipolarity, a “horizontal” model with a community of states aided by common values and principles and supported by international institutions could work better at integrating individual, sovereign nation-states into a meaningful community to grant “global citizenship.”
Blake, p. 272 “The principle I defend, therefore, mandates the following: that all individuals, regardless of institutional context, ought to have access to those goods and circumstances under which they are able to live as rationally autonomous agents, capable of selecting and pursuing plans of life in accordance with individual conceptions of the good. There are, I think, several methods by which people might be denied the circumstances of autonomy; famine, extreme poverty, crippling social norms such as caste hierarchies-all of these structures seem comprehensible as violations of a liberal principle devoted to the defense of the circumstances of autonomy, although I cannot here defend these claims in detail. It is enough in the present context to notice that a consistent liberal must be as concerned with poverty abroad as that at home, since borders provide no insulation from the demands of a morality based upon the worth of all autonomous human beings.”; Nagel, p. 118 “I assume there is some minimal concern we owe to fellow human beings threatened with starvation or severe malnutrition and early death from easily preventable diseases, as all these people in dire poverty are. Although there is plenty of room for disagreement about the most effective methods, some form of humane assistance from the well-off to those in extremis is clearly called for quite apart from any demand of justice, if we are not simply ethical egoists.”; Sangiovanni, p. 5 “I will assume that all plausible criteria of distributive justice, whether national, international, or global, must at least require raising all human beings to a minimal threshold defined in terms of access to basic goods, including clothing, shelter, food, and sanitation. Although I cannot defend this stipulation in any detail here, all of the major forms of ‘internationalism’[…] accept it as a starting point.”
“Those rights, if they exist, set universal and prepolitical limits to the legitimate use of power, independent of special forms of association. It is wrong for any individual or group to deny such rights to any other individual or group, and we do not give them up as a condition of membership in a political society, even though their precise boundaries and methods of protection through law will have to be determined politically in light of each society's particular circumstances.” Nagel, p. 127, my italics. I agree with Nagel to the point that I also hold rights to be played out in accordance to particular circumstances, but without a more substantial world order based on non-domination I think it is hardly conceivable of a way to determine these rights' “precise boundaries” without letting powerful private and public agents abuse them and twist them according to their interests.
I think it is interesting to report that while a Google search gives almost 200 million entries for the word “sovereignty,” it yields less than a million when one search for the plural “sovereignties.” Sovereignty has historically presented itself as absolute, and dictionaries reflect the difficulty of reappraising it. See next section on the “inclusive exception” as a paradigm of sovereignty.
As evidenced by the current polarization and paralysis in many multilateral bodies in the context of the Collective West-China/Russia confrontation, and the outdated structure of international institutions, in particular with a view to equal and democratic participation.
As Nagel (p. 126) says “If the conditions of even the poorest societies should come to meet a livable minimum, the political conception might not even see a general humanitarian claim for redistribution.” The question is on who has the authority to define that minimum. I think non-domination requires that this is not settled arbitrarily, but that all those over whom this minimum is imposed have a say about it. There is no way to discuss these matters until even the poorest states are heeded globally as respectfully as minorities are within democratic, egalitarian nation-states. It is not because of the problem of “relative deprivation,” but in order to enable everyone to reach a “livable minimum,” which Nagel's analysis presupposes, that we have to challenge the present international order. By saying “international order,” I refer also to issues like asylum, migrants' rights, and criteria for citizenship which arise within the national borders.
E.g. in Nagel's “political approach” and Blake's “institutional theory.” “Another sort of attitude would prompt one to ask not what institutions we ought to have, but what the institutions we currently have would have to do to be justified. This sort of theory – which I call institutional theory – would take much more of the world as a pretheoretical given for purposes of analysis.” Blake, p. 262. “Unlike cosmopolitanism, the second conception of justice does not have a standard name, but let me call it the political conception, since it is exemplified by Rawls's view that justice should be understood as a specifically political value, rather than being derived from a comprehensive moral system, so that it is essentially a virtue – the first virtue – of social institutions. On the political conception, sovereign states are not merely instruments for realizing the preinstitutional value of justice among human beings. Instead, their existence is precisely what gives the value of justice its application, by putting the fellow citizens of a sovereign state into a relation that they do not have with the rest of humanity, an institutional relation which must then be evaluated by the special standards of fairness and equality that fill out the content of justice.” Nagel, p. 120. I find this neutralization of the critical potential of moral theory – as opposed to “institutional” political theory – to be a problematic radicalization of positivism.
Nagel foresaw this remark about “an unrealistically sharp dichotomy between sovereign states and existing global institutions.” For the details of his dealing with this objection and with the idea of “a sliding standard of obligation” (which he deems implausible) see “The Problem of Global Justice,” pp. 141; 143.
Ahiwa Ong, Neoliberalism as Exception: Mutations in Citizenship and Sovereignty, (Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2006), see especially chap. 4.
Migration is considered specifically problematic within discourses on global justice: “J. Donald Moon and others have pressed on me the objection that the entire international system might be based upon coercion, seen, for instance, in the coercive exclusion of would-be immigrants at the border. This may be correct, but it is important to remember that each distinct form of coercion requires a distinct form of justification. The refusal of entry to a would-be member may or may not be justifiable; the form such justification would take, however, would be significantly different from that offered to a present member for the web of legal coercion within which she currently lives.” M. Blake, “State, Autonomy and Coercion”, note 30, my italics. See also Nagel, pp. 129–130.
Famously, Giorgio Agamben has criticized the concentration camp as a paradigm of modern politics: Homo Sacer. Il potere sovrano e la nuda vita (Torino: Einaudi, 1995), pp. 185–201 “Il campo come nómos del moderno.”
“To insiders, the state says: Yes, we coerce you, but we do so in accordance with principles you could not reasonably reject. To outsiders, it says: We do not coerce you, and therefore do not apply our principles of liberal justice to you - although you do have an entitlement to the preconditions of autonomous functioning, and we will ensure that these are provided to you if you do not have them now.” Blake, “Distributive justice”, p. 287.
“This is a powerful line of argument, and I believe that my analysis of the voluntary/nonvoluntary distinction strengthens it: noncompliance or exit from most major international organizations, let alone the global institutional order as a whole, carries significant costs for states subject to them, especially smaller and less powerful ones. It stretches credibility to argue that these costs are small enough to make membership voluntary in the relevant sense, and hence to suspend a concern with distributive justice. Belonging to the WTO, UN, IMF, EU, and so on, is not like belonging to the local tennis club.” Sangiovanni, “Global Justice, Reciprocity.” p. 19. The coercive power of international institutions on a developing country like Jamaica is documented emblematically in Life and Debt, a film by Stephanie Black. Confront also with what Joshua Cohen and Charles Sabel say in their answer to Nagel in “Extra Rempublicam Nulla Justitia”, issue 34 (2006) pp. 147–175.
The market capitalization of Wall Street's “Magnificent Seven” (Microsoft (MSFT), Apple (AAPL), Alphabet (GOOGL) (GOOG), Amazon.com (AMZN), Nvidia (NVDA) and Tesla (TSLA)) seem to be around three times the GDP of Germany.
But these could also be seen as opposite coercive phenomena: a state coerces another to dismantle terrorist activities, but the latter was already coercing the former when not impeding terrorists from planning attacks abroad. So even if these interventions were all genuinely justified, the problem of the fact of international coercion would remain. The question is merely who is the victim of the coercion, and who is the culprit.
Compare with Nagel's conclusive “speculation”: “The Problem[…]” pp. 146–147.
Bohman, “Living Without Freedom”, pp. 545–547.
The establishment of such standards of course is a question of justice, and a very important one. In what follows I will rely on Jeremy Waldron's argument for natural duties to cast light on the other side of the demands of justice. Nagel's specific defense of a two-tier distributive criterion seems relatively compatible with Waldron's analysis of the natural justification of political institutions. According to Waldron: “Once again, this [the existence of a natural duty holding between an individual and her own national institutions] is not incompatible with theories of consent or fair play [see the role played by reciprocity in Nagel's argument]. Maybe there are many layers to the moral issue of what one owes to the state.” Jeremy Waldron, “Special Ties and Natural Duties”, in Thomas Pogge and Darrel Moellendorf (eds.) Global Justice: Seminal Essays (Saint Paul: Paragon House, 2008), p. 398 (my italics). What Waldron says in this article applies only in part to the case of supranational institutions: but Waldron's view seems also not to be explicitly against such an extended application to these political problems. Moreover, Waldron's argument is intrinsically transnational.
True, Rawsl's theory is famously “a reasonable conception of justice for the basic structure of society conceived for the time being as a closed system isolated from other societies” (A Theory of Justice, p. 8). But Waldron remarks that “the assumption that justice may be confined within the borders of a single society is unsatisfactory” (“Special Ties”, p. 400). He put forward two examples as evidence of this: the outrageous disparities between, say, New Zealand and Bangladesh, and the power of influence and even of killing that a sovereign state exercised within the territory of another in the Rainbow Warrior Affair. This latter is also a graphic example of what I meant by questioning the assumption that coercion is exercised only inside national territory by the legitimate authority. But by leaving aside these topics, Rawls himself left the door open for the reassessment of the obligations of justice in writing that “[The duty of justice] also constrains us to further just arrangements not yet established, at least when this can be done without too much cost to ourselves” (A Theory of Justice, p. 115; confront with Waldron, pp. 392–393). The compliance to just institutions is to be flanked by the strive for bringing about those still lacking. See the duties I resumed in the previous paragraph, and the corresponding articles in the Universal Declaration.
This issue is the main focus of Waldron's article: see for example “Special Ties”, pp. 409–410.
Against the objection pointing to the contingency of particular ties in a theory of natural duties see ibidem, p. 404.
Despite his much more optimistic idea of human nature, Kant was equally persuaded that even “good nature and righteous” persons living without “a public lawful state” would not be able to avoid “fighting” and “wild violence.” Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, trans. John Ladd (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965) section 42, p. 71, 76. See the discussion in Waldron, pp. 400–401, and also the first chapter in Benhabib, The Rights of Others, providing an accurate analysis of Kant's cosmopolitanism.
As Waldron puts it: “If anything, such violence will be worse than that of the Hobbesian “war of all against all” because the battles will be better organized. The moral interest in reducing such fighting provides a reason for all of us to join and support the same organization[…]” “Special Ties”, p. 407.
The “domestic analogy” has been criticized by realists, to my view correctly, as a misleading perspective on international politics.
The example is again drawn from Waldron, “Special Ties.”
“Certainly such resolutions are provisional. As the sphere of human interaction expands, further conflicts may arise, and the scope of the legal framework must be extended and if necessary rethought, according to the same Kantian principle.” (Waldron, “Special Ties”, p. 401). The principle may be “Kantian” or otherwise: what matters is that institutions concerned with global justice are not to be opposed to local cooperation, which they may even boost.
“It is morally imperative that the demands of justice be pursued period. If institutions are necessary for their pursuit, then it is morally imperative that such institutions be established.” Ibidem, p. 412.
This is true if Waldron's arguments for natural duties are correct and if there is no alternative capable of providing the same benefit to the strengthening of the international polity, due to the twofold characteristics of justice which apply to an institution: namely that (1) it must be just in the way it operates (one could call this a “formal requirement”) and (2) that it must be doing something that justice requires (one could call this other a “substantive requirement.” See Waldron, “Special Ties[…]” pp. 413–414). The latter characteristic involves an empirical evaluation over the possibility of achieving the same outcomes within a system of independent states, but I believe this idea has been implicitly abandoned by independent states themselves from the creation of the League of the Nations on. See next section. The requirements of (1) are already demanding, for it seems to me that if we are to take seriously the justifications of democratic sovereignty, something more akin to it should be pursued in the international arena as regards especially direct participation, the separation of powers, equality of voice, and an effective power of coercion which, as in the case of sovereign states, is not to be confounded with violence: it has rather to do with the relevance, reliability and fairness of the sanctions and incentives.
Thomas Nagel. (2005). “The Problem of Global Justice.” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 33(3), 113–147.
As I said above, Waldron's description of the “state of nature” is the classic one we find in the Hobbesian tradition.
See Waldron, “Special Ties”, p. 409: “In most cases, the fact that there is a state and that it is, for all practical purposes, dominant and unchallenged in a territory will be sufficient. This is the organization that deserves our support in the enterprise of doing justice if any organization does.” The fact that the organization has just ends is not in itself sufficient to grant allegiance to it (ibid., p. 406) because effectiveness matters and no one is bound to “lost causes” (ibid., p. 405). This explains enduring loyalty to a country that is partly corrupt and unjust. It seems reasonable that there must be a considerable amount of injustice before a revolution becomes preferable. And the fact that there is such a red line witnesses to the reasonableness of overthrowing tyranny once that this limit has been surpassed. What is of moral relevance here is not only the quantity or the gravity of the state's flaws, but also the preconditions upon which an alternative might be established.
“Unjust and illegitimate regimes are the necessary precursors of the progress toward legitimacy and democracy, because they create the centralized power that can then be contested, and perhaps turned in other directions without being destroyed[…] The global scope of justice will expand only through developments that first increase the injustice of the world by introducing effective but illegitimate institutions to which the standards of justice apply, standards by which we may hope they will eventually be transformed.” Nagel, “The Problem”, pp. 146–147. The question, once again, is what amount of coercive and unjust power we are to put up with before its sources are made accountable to the democratic process.
“Phusis” and “Nomos” in the vocabulary of the Sophists: according to Agamben Hobbes's state of nature is not to be interpreted as an existing historical step, but as an internal condition of the sovereign power that was only more apparent in a time of civil wars. See Giorgio Agamben, “Homo Sacer”, pp. 40–42.
Agamben thinks that two different concepts of “life,” which the Greeks called bios and zoe, are now conflated into the all-embracing sphere of politics. See Homo Sacer, Introduction.
For a more specific discussion on freedom see chapter 3, and the bibliography mentioned there.
A statement that could be translated as “freedom is citizenship,” or also “freedom is (in) civilization.” Cicero, Pro Balbo, 9.24.
Homo Sacer, pp. 97–101.
Carl Schmitt, Politic Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans. By G. Schwab (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005), p. 5.
“Yet in thinking about the future, we should keep in mind that political power is rarely created as a result of demands for legitimacy, and that there is little reason to think that things will be different in this case. If we look at the historical development of conceptions of justice and legitimacy for the nation-state, it appears that sovereignty usually precedes legitimacy.” See “The Problem of Global Justice”, p. 145.
In Schmitt's conception of sovereignty, we can have even a private sovereign, a private force which is capable of dehumanizing persons by abandoning them, like in the cases of places ruled by tribes, terrorism, or Heart of Darkness-like exploitation.
By “natural” I mean here that some political regimes tend to suggest that the way they receive and exercise power does not require any justification: it is presented as a mere fact, and an unalterable one. Sovereignty, not only in general but as wielded by this or that particular sovereign, is presented as a requirement of human nature, or of nature itself. This is most blatantly the case with monarchs “of divine right,” and the like.
I use this word in the broad sense of a general, constitutional agreement on who protects, who is protected, and at what conditions.
Waldron brilliantly argues for the universality not only of natural duties, but also of special ties, since the latter obviously involve a universal request to refrain from interference (see note 93). This, in my opinion, explains many difficulties arising in cases of “humanitarian interventions”: not only sovereignty requires delimiting, but delimiting (to some extent) is intrinsically a “sovereign” act.
To temper this dilemma, one could consider theories of rights as a “common concern” – Charles Beitz. (2001). “Human Rights as a Common Concern.” American Political Science Review, 95(2), 269–282 – they can be rights in a “manifesto sense” – Joel Feinberg, Social Philosophy (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1973), and as such different from prohibitions. A global regime of human rights, in this case, would imply something much thinner than a global governance. But the possibility, or rather, the fact of international coercion would remain unresolved and problematic.
Admittedly, this is not the case with all the instances of sovereignty. Sovereignty did in fact employ a variety of legitimizing strategies in human history and across geography.
I refer here again to a theory such as Waldron's. It must be stressed that according to his theory the existence of a sovereign of some sort is justified, while the legitimacy of this or that individual regime is always opened to challenge.
This seems to me the crux of the argument advanced by Bohman, “Living Without Freedom.”
Bonnie Honig, Democracy and the Foreigner (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001).
Honig suggests to transform citizenship from a status administered by the central institution to “a practice in which denizens, migrants, and their allies hold states accountable for their definitions and distribution of goods, powers, rights, freedoms, privileges, and justice,” ibid., p. 104.
By this term I do not refer only to the integration of foreigners into their hosting citizenry, but also to the integration of states into a sufficiently harmonic global community and world-order.
This seems to be the meaning of the quote by Kierkegaard that opens Dora Kostakopoulou's work on citizenship: “The irony of life is that it is lived forward, but understood backward.” Dora Kostakopoulou, The Future Governance of Citizenship (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), p. 1. Confronts also with her definition of (national) culture as a “3P-Plex”: Practice, Process, and Project (ibid., p. 64).
I think the very existence of common, or precedent, law suggests that it would be more appropriate to focus on how practices generate laws, and laws stabilize practices (but the relation, on some occasion, could work the other way round) than opposing the two as though the concepts were independent.
Peter Nyers. (2003). “Abject Cosmopolitanism. The Politics of Protection in the Anti-Deportation Movement.” Third World Quarterly, 24(6), 1069–1093.
I owe this awareness also to a remark by professor Gershon Shafir.
“Meta” politics is an ambiguous term: I am referring to political authorities which go beyond the traditional ones, namely national sovereigns. One could say that this is just the most recent evolution of politics itself.
In this way, every refugee literally realizes the oxymoron employed by Nyers (see ibid., pp. 1072–1075), especially if seen from the standpoint of international law: they are citizens of the world because they are momentarily citizens of nowhere, they are cosmopolitan inasmuch as they are “abject” (in the literal sense of the word, which according to the Oxford Dictionary originated from “late Middle English (in the sense ‘rejected’): from Latin abjectus, past participle of abicere ‘reject’, from ab- ‘away’ +jacere ‘to throw’.” The term is in this acceptation synonymous to “uprooted.”
Historically, because if Agamben is correct the sovereign has presented itself as the dominator over “states of exceptions”, the arbitrator over exclusion and inclusion. So before humanity reached an awareness of universal human rights, sovereignty, and the citizenship status that only the sovereign could concede and secure, was first and foremost a right to exist, a set of human rights. But this is also conceptually true if Hobbes is right in holding that the sovereign always gets its legitimation by avoiding that subjects fall (again) in the state of nature. If so, Waldron's idea of natural duties is, as it presents itself, an explanation of the core justification of citizenship and “special ties” as purveyors of human rights. I leave aside for the moment additional particularities and sentimental allegiances pertaining to the field of nationalism: they will be given some space in the next two chapters.
See David Owen, “In Loco Civitatis: On the Normative Basis of the Institution of Refugeehood and Responsibilities for Refugees”, in Sarah Fine and Lea Ypi (eds.) Migration in Political Theory: The Ethics of Movement and Membership (Oxford, 2016; online edn., Oxford Academic, March 24, 2016), https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199676606.003.0013. Accessed February 5, 2024.
I hold that not only Waldron, but also Rawls thinks that we have such a duty, and that it constitutes, we could say, about “half” of the requirements of justice. But note that the other “half,” as Nagel acknowledges, namely distributive justice avoiding relative deprivation, presupposes the creation of just institutions. Therefore, the duty to bring about just institutions for everyone is morally necessary, but not sufficient, and the “two sides of justice,” so to speak, are intertwined.
Nyers, “Abject Cosmopolitanism”, p. 1081.
Perspective Eurocentrism is here accidental and should not be misunderstood for some form of exceptionalism. I believe other supranational or federated states would give us as many suggestions as this case.
Empires which destabilized democratic institutions at home (as in the case of the Algerian war) or fueled non-democratic regimes (like Spain's and Portugal's).
For a classic account of the historical-ideological roots of Europe, see Federico Chabod, Storia dell'idea d'Europa (Roma: Laterza, 1965).
Immanuel Kant, Perpetual Peace, ed. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill 1997); Jürgen Habermas, “Kant's Idea of a Perpetual Peace, with the Benefit of Two Hundred Year's Hindsight”, in Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant's Cosmopolitan Ideal (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1997), pp. 113–153.
See for example Monnet's speech delivered in Algeri on August 5, 1943 “There will be no peace in Europe, if the states are reconstituted on the basis of national sovereignty… The countries of Europe are too small to guarantee their peoples the necessary prosperity and social development. The European states must constitute themselves into a federation…” European States being “too small” is in my eyes an issue that can be applied to any nation-state now that globalization has developed. Every country is “too small” to “do it alone,” when confronted with the immense potential for individual and collective development.
This will be the aim of the fourth chapter.
This is the main theme of the third chapter.
- Prelims
- Chapter 1 Introduction: Theorizing Citizenship in Critical Times
- Chapter 2 Fundamental Rights: The Right to Have Rights
- Chapter 3 Citizenship or the Right to Be Equal
- Chapter 4 The Right to Freedom, World Citizenship, and Global Peace
- Chapter 5 Conclusion: From Parts to Whole
- Bibliography
- Index