Subcommuting and comparable iterative roots of order preserving homeomorphisms

Veerapazham Murugan (Department of Mathematical and Computational Sciences, National Institute of Technology Karnataka, Surathkal, Mangalore, India)
Murugan Suresh Kumar (Department of Mathematics, The Gandhigram Rural Institute, Gandhigram, India)

Arab Journal of Mathematical Sciences

ISSN: 1319-5166

Article publication date: 31 October 2019

Issue publication date: 31 August 2020

396

Abstract

It is known that the iterative roots of continuous functions are not necessarily unique, if it exist. In this note, by introducing the set of points of coincidence, we study the iterative roots of order preserving homeomorphisms. In particular, we prove a characterization of identical iterative roots of an order preserving homeomorphism using the points of coincidence of functions.

Keywords

Citation

Murugan, V. and Suresh Kumar, M. (2020), "Subcommuting and comparable iterative roots of order preserving homeomorphisms", Arab Journal of Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 26 No. 1/2, pp. 203-210. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ajmsc.2019.10.003

Publisher

:

Emerald Publishing Limited

Copyright © 2019, Veerapazham Murugan and Murugan Suresh Kumar

License

Published in Arab Journal of Mathematical Sciences. Published by Emerald Publishing Limited. This article is published under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY 4.0) license. Anyone may reproduce, distribute, translate and create derivative works of this article (for both commercial and non-commercial purposes), subject to full attribution to the original publication and authors. The full terms of this license may be seen at http://creativecommons.org/licences/by/4.0/legalcode


1. Introduction

Given a function F:XX and a positive integer n, if there is a function f:XX such that

(1)fn(x)=F(x),for allxX
(where fn is n times composition of f ) then f is called an n th iterative root or fractional iterate of order n of F. The problem of finding the iterative root of functions was initiated in the classical works of Charles Babbage [1]. The iterative roots of continuous monotone and piecewise monotone function was developed in the works of Bödewadt [2], Łojasiewicz [7], Kuczma [4], Zhang [6,12] and many others. For a detailed study of recent results on iterative roots of continuous piecewise monotone functions can be found in the survey paper by Zdun and Solarz [11].

For the class of strictly increasing continuous functions, we have the following result.

Theorem 1.1 ([5]). Let I be any interval. Then every strictly increasing continuous function F from I into itself possesses a strictly increasing continuous iterative roots of order n, for all n.

Theorem 1.1 guarantees the existence of strictly increasing continuous iterative roots of a strictly increasing continuous functions. Moreover, this strictly increasing continuous nth order iterative root depends on arbitrary strictly increasing homeomorphisms (see Theorem 11.2.2 [5]), and hence its iterative roots are not necessarily unique. In fact, every strictly increasing continuous function, other than identity, possesses infinitely many strictly increasing continuous nth order iterative roots.

In fact, uniqueness of iterative roots of a special class of monotonic functions was conjectured by Bödewadt [2] and answered in negative by Smajdor [9]. Motivated by Bödewadt, suppose f and g are two iterative roots of order n of a strictly increasing homeomorphism F (i.e. fn=gn=F ), it is reasonable to ask under what condition f and g are identically equal?

It is known that, if fn=gn=F and f,g commutes each other (i.e. fg=gf ) then f must be equal to g (see [10]). In this article, we further investigate this problem. We give some sufficient conditions, using the set of points of coincidence of two functions. Also, for given order preserving homeomorphism from an interval onto itself, by generalizing the result in [10], we characterize the conditions of identical iterative roots of an order preserving homeomorphism.

2. Set of points of coincidence

Throughout our discussion we fix I=(a,b), where ab, and H(I) denotes the set of all order preserving homeomorphisms from I onto itself. Here after we always assume all the functions are in the class H(I) unless otherwise stated.

Let f and g be two order preserving homeomorphisms from the interval I onto JI. We say f and g are comparable, if either f(x)g(x) or g(x)f(x) for all xI, and if the inequalities are strict then we say f and g are strictly comparable.

Proposition 2.1. If f and g are two strictly comparable order preserving homeomorphisms from I onto JI, then fn and gn are strictly comparable order preserving homeomorphisms, for all n. In addition to that, if J=I then fn and gn are also strictly comparable order preserving homeomorphisms, for all n.

Proof. First we prove the result for positive integers using induction on n. Assume f(x)<g(x) for all xI. Suppose there exists tf(I) such that f2(t)g2(t). Since f(t)<g(t) we have f(f(t))<f(g(t)). Therefore

g(g(t))f(f(t))<f(g(t)).
i.e.,(fg)(g(t))>0.
Since (fg)(t)<0, by intermediate value theorem there exists c(t,g(t)) such that f(c)=g(c), which is a contradiction. Hence f2<g2 on (a,b).

Assume fk(x)<gk(x) for all x(a,b) and 1kn1. Suppose there is a tfn1(I) such that

fn(t)gn(t).
Since fn1(t)<gn1(t) we have fn(t)<f(gn1(t)). Therefore
gn(t)fn(t)<f(gn1(t)).
i.e.,(fg)(gn1(t))>0.
Since (fg)(t)<0, by intermediate value theorem there exists c(t,gn1(t)) such that f(c)=g(c), which is a contradiction. Hence fn<gn on (a,b).

Now, we prove the result for negative integers by assuming J=I. First we prove if f(x)<g(x) for all xI, then g1(x)<f1(x) for all xI. Suppose there is a tI such that g1(t)f1(t). If g1(t)=f1(t) then there exists xI such that f(x)=g(x)=t, which is not possible as f(x)<g(x) for all xI. Therefore g1(t)>f1(t). But this implies

f(g1(t))>t>g(f1(t)).
Since f(g1(t))<g(g1(t)) we have t>f(g1(t))>t, which is a contradiction. Thus g1(x)<f1(x) for all xI. Therefore, as above gn(x)<fn(x) for all xI and for all n. □

For any two functions f and g, we denote the set of points of coincidence of f and g by Z(f,g). i.e., Z(f,g)={xI|f(x)=g(x)}.

Theorem 2.2. If Z(f,g) is a finite set, then fngn for all n\{0}.

Proof. If Z(f,g) is empty, then either f(x)<g(x) or g(x)<f(x) for all xI. Therefore by Proposition 2.1, gn(x)fn(x) for all xI and for all n\{0}.

On the other hand, if Z(f,g) is non empty, we argue as follows:

If f and g do not have a common fixed point, then there exists tI such that f(t)=t but g(t)t. Without loss of generality, let g(t)<t. Therefore gn(t)<t but fn(t)=t which in turn implies fngn for all n.

If f and g have common fixed points, then the set {xI|f(x)=g(x)=x} must be finite. Let αi where 1ik be the common fixed points of f and g with

a=α0<α1<<αk<αk+1=b.
Now, to prove our result it is enough to prove fngn on (αi,αi+1) for some i. Since on each (αi,αi+1) both the functions f and g are self maps and has no fixed points, we may assume f and g do not have fixed points in I.

Case 1. x<f(x) and g(x)<x for all xI.

Since g(x)<x<f(x) for all x(a,b), for any positive integer n, gn(x)<x<fn(x). Moreover for any positive integer n, fn(x)<x<gn(x) for all x(a,b) as f1(x)<x<g1(x) for all x(a,b). Hence for any n\{0}, fngn.

Case 2. x<f(x) and x<g(x) for all xI.

Step 1: We prove the result for positive integers.

Let α=max{x(a,b)|f(x)=g(x)}, then f(α)=g(α) and f(x)g(x) for all x(α,b). Without loss of generality assume f(x)<g(x) for all x(α,b). To prove fngn on I, we prove fn<gn on (α,b) for all n.

Since f and g are self maps on (α,b), By Proposition 2.1, fn(x)<gn(x) for all x(α,b).

Step 2: We prove the result for negative integers.

Let β=min{x(a,b)|f(x)=g(x)}, then f(β)=g(β) and f(x)g(x) for all x(a,β). We may assume f(x)<g(x) for all x(a,β). Since

(2)x<f(x)<g(x)for allx(a,β),
replacing x by g1(x) in Eq. (2) we get g1(x)<f(g1(x))<x for all x(a,g1(β)). In particular,
(3)g1(x)<f1(x)for allx(a,g1(β)).
To prove fngn on I, we prove gn<fn on (a,g1(β)) for all n. Since, both f1 and g1 are self maps on (a,g1(β)), by Proposition 2.1, gn(x)<fn(x) for all x(a,g1(β)).

Moreover the cases f(x)<x and x<g(x) for all xI and f(x)<x and g(x)<x for all xI are similar to case 1 and case 2. □

Lemma 2.3. If fg=gf , then fngm=gmfn for all n,m .

Proof. First we prove fng=gfn for all n. As f and g commute, we see that

f2g=f(fg)=f(gf)=(gf)f=gf2.
Assume fkg=gfk for all 1kn1. Again, by using induction hypothesis and f and g commute, we see that
gfn=(gfn1)f=(fn1g)f=fn1(gf)=fn1(fg)=fng.
Therefore fng=gfn for all n. Since gf=fg, pre-multiplying by f1 we get f1gf=g. Now, post multiply by f1 to get f1g=gf1. Hence by repeating the above process we get fng=gfn. Therefore fng=gfn for all n.

Since fng=gfn for each n, again by above argument, we have fngm=gmfn for all m. □

Proposition 2.4. If xZ(f,g) and fg=gf, then fn(x),gn(x)Z(f,g) for all n.

Proof. For xZ(f,g), we have f(f(x))=f(g(x))=g(f(x)). Therefore f(x)Z(f,g). By repeating the above process we see that fn(x)Z(f,g) for all n. Now, by applying Lemma 2.3, we see that

f(f1(x))=f1(f(x))=f1(g(x))=g(f1(x)).
Therefore f1(x)Z(f,g). Hence, by above argument, fn(x)Z(f,g) for all n. i.e., fn(x)Z(f,g) for all n. Similarly gn(x)Z(f,g) for all n. □

Theorem 2.5. If fg=gf , then Z(f,g)=Z(fn,gn) for all n\{0}

Proof. Step 1: We prove Z(f,g)=Z(fn,gn) for all n using induction on n. First we prove Z(f,g)=Z(f2,g2).

For xZ(f,g), we have

f2(x)=f(f(x))=f(g(x))=g(f(x))=g(g(x))=g2(x).
Let xZ(f2,g2). If f(x)g(x), without loss of generality, say f(x)<g(x) then
f2(x)<f(g(x))=g(f(x))=g2(x)
which is not possible. Therefore Z(f,g)=Z(f2,g2).

Assume Z(f,g)=Z(fk,gk) for 2kn1. Therefore, by applying Proposition 2.4, for xZ(f,g), we have

fn(x)=fn1(f(x))=fn1(g(x))=gn1(g(x)).
This shows that Z(f,g)Z(fn,gn). Suppose xZ(fn,gn) with f(x)<g(x). Then, by applying Lemma 2.3
fn(x)<fn1(g(x))=gn1(f(x))=g(gn1(x))=gn(x),
which is not possible. Therefore Z(fn,gn)Z(f,g). This completes the proof of step 1.

Step 2: We prove Z(f,g)=Z(fn,gn) for all n.

It is clear from Step 1 that, Z(f1,g1)=Z(fn,gn) for all n. Therefore to prove Step 2, it is enough to prove Z(f,g)=Z(f1,g1).

Let xZ(f,g). Suppose f1(x)<g1(x). Then, by applying Lemma 2.3 we see that,

x<f(g1(x))=g1(f(x))=g1(g(x))=x.
which is not possible. On the other hand, if g1(x)<f1(x) then
x<g(f1(x))=f1(g(x))=f1(f(x))=x,
again a contradiction. Therefore f1(x)=g1(x) whenever f(x)=g(x), i.e. Z(f,g)Z(f1,g1). Now by replacing f and g by f1 and g1 respectively, we get Z(f,g)=Z(f1,g1). □

Corollary 2.6. If f,g satisfy fg=gf and fn=gn for some nZ then f=g.

Proof. Since fg=gf, by Theorem 2.5, we have Z(fn,gn)=Z(f,g). But Z(fn,gn)=I as fn=gn. Therefore f=g on I. □

Theorem 2.7. Let f,gH(I) without fixed points such that fg=gf . Suppose Z(fn,gn) is an interval for some n , then f=g on I.

Proof. Since fg=gf, by Theorem 2.5, Z(f,g)=Z(fn,gn). Without loss of generality, let αZ(f,g) such that α<f(α). Also by Proposition 2.4, f(α)Z(f,g). Since fm(α)b and fm(α)a as m. Therefore

I=(a,b)=m[fm(α),fm+1(α)].
Let y[fm(α),fm+1(α)] be arbitrary. Then there is an element x[α,f(α)] such that y=fn(x). Since f=g on [α,f(α)] we have y=fm(x)=gm(x). Therefore, by Lemma 2.3,
f(y)=f(gm(x))=gm(f(x))=gm(g(x))=g(gm(x))=g(y).
This completes the proof. □

3. Subcommuting and comparable iterative roots

Definition 3.1 ([3]). Let f and g be two order preserving homeomorphisms on I. We say f subcommutes with g if f(g(x))g(f(x)), for all xI.

Note that every commuting functions are subcommuting, but the converse is not necessarily true. For example, consider the functions f,g:(0,)(0,) by f(x)=2x and g(x)=x2. Clearly f subcommutes with g as f(g(x))=2x2g(f(x))=4x2 for all x(0,). But f(g(x))=2x2g(f(x))=4x2 for all x(0,).

Let F:II be an order preserving homeomorphism. We prove that it is not possible to have different iterative roots of F which are either comparable or subcommuting.

Theorem 3.2. Let FH(I). Suppose f,gH(I) satisfy fn=gn=F for some n. Then the following are equivalent.

  • 1. f subcommutes with g.

  • 2. f and g are comparable.

  • 3. f=g.

Proof. 3 implies 1 and 2 are trivial.

(13) In view of Corollary 2.6, it is enough to prove that fg=gf on I.

Suppose fg(x)<gf(x) for some x. Then

gn+1(x)=gn(g(x))=fn(g(x))=fn1(f(g(x)))<fn1(g(f(x)))fn2(g(f2(x)))g(fn(x))=gn+1(x).
i.e., gn+1(x)<gn+1(x), a contradiction. Hence fg=gf. Therefore by Corollary 2.6, f=g on I.

(23) Assume fg. If possible, let f(t)g(t) for some tI, therefore f(t)<g(t). Since fn=gn, we have

gn(t)=fn(t)<fn1(g(t))g(fn2(g(t))),
where the last inequality holds since fg. But then gn1(t)<fn2(g(t)) as g1 is an order-preserving homeomorphisms. Now
gn1(t)<fn2(g(t))g(fn3(g(t))),
since fg. This implies gn2(t)<fn3(g(t)), since g1 is an order-preserving homeomorphisms. Continuing this process up to (n2) times we get
g(g(t))<f(g(t)),
a contradiction to our assumption. Therefore f=g on I. □

Part of a theorem due to McShane [8] is observed below.

Corollary 3.3 ([8]). The only order preserving iterative root of any order of the identity function on is the identity function.

Proof. Clearly, identity function is an iterative root of any order of the identity function, it follows from Theorem 3.2, that any order preserving homeomorphism whose iteration is identity becomes identity, as the identity function subcommutes (also commutes, so Corollary 2.6 also applicable) with any function. □

Further, if fH(I) such that fn(x)=x for all xI but f is not the identity, then there exists an interval (α,β) such that either f(x)<x or f(x)>x for all x(α,β) and f((α,β))=(α,β). Since fn(x)=x for all x(α,β) and f is comparable with identity, by Theorem 3.2 f(x)=x on (α,β), which is a contradiction. This forces that identity is the only order preserving homeomorphism of the identity function.

From Theorem 3.2, we can conclude that the non-commuting, non-comparable iterative roots of an order preserving homeomorphism are all different. We provide an illustrative example. The construction given in this example is based on Theorem 11.2.2 in [5].

Example 1. Consider the order preserving homeomorphism F:[0,1][0,1] defined by

F(x)={4xifx[0,18)43x+13ifx[18,14)49x+59ifx[14,1].
In order to construct iterative roots of this function, first we define a sequence of disjoint intervals whose union is [0,1] and on each interval we define homeomorphism which serves as an iterative root of order 2 of F.

To start with, let x0=18 and x1=14. Define x2k:=F(x2k2),x2k+1:=F(x2k1) for all k and x(2k+1):=F1(x(2k1)),x2k:=F1(x(2k2)) for all k{0}. Note that x2=F(x0)=12;x3=F(x1)=23;x4=F(x2)=12(49)+59;x5=F(x3)=23(49)+59, in general

x2k=12(49)k1+59i=0k2(49)i,x2k+1=23(49)k1+59i=0k2(49)ik,
and x1=F1(x1)=14(14);x2=F1(x0)=18(14);x3=F1(x1)=14(14)2;x4=F1(x2)=18(14)2, in general
x(2k+1)=14(14)k+1,x2k=18(14)kk{0}.

Define Ik=[xk,xk+1] for k. Since x2k1,x2k+11,x2k0, x(2k+1)0 as k we have kIk=[0,1]. Let ϕ0:I0I1 be the homeomorphism defined by 0(x)=2x for all xI0. Now, define ϕk:IkIk+1 by ϕk(x)=Fϕk11(x) for all xIk and k, also define ϕk:IkI(k1) by ϕk(x)=ϕ(k1)1F(x) for all xIk and k. Consider the homeomorphism f:[0,1][0,1] defined by f(x)=ϕk(x) if xIk for all k. By calculation we can show that

f(x)={2xifx[0,14)23x+13ifx[14,1].
and f2(x)=F(x)x[0,1]. Now we construct another order preserving homeomorphism g which do not subcommute and not comparable with f but g2=F. For this, let ψ0:I0I1 be the homeomorphism defined by
ψ0(x)={x+18ifx[18,316)3x14ifx[316,14].
Now, define ψk:IkIk+1 by ψk(x)=Fψk11(x) for all xIk and k, also define ψk:IkI(k1) by ψk(x)=ψ(k1)1F(x) for all xIk and k. Then the homeomorphism g:[0,1][0,1] defined by g(x)=ψk(x) if xIk for all k satisfies g2(x)=F(x) for all x[0,1]. Since,
ψ1(x)=Fψ01(x)={43x+16ifx[14,516)49x+49ifx[516,12],
and
ψ2(x)=Fψ11(x)={13x+12ifx[12,712)x+19ifx[712,23],

we observe that

f(g(316))=f(ψ0(316))=f(516)=1324<g(f(316))=ψ1(38)=1118,
and
g(f(1332))=ψ2(2948)=103144<f(g(1332))=f(ψ1(1332))=f(4572)=2736.

Moreover, g(316)=516<f(316)=38 and f(516)=1324<g(516)=712 . Thus we have two order preserving homeomorphisms f and g such that they are neither comparable nor subcommuting but f2=g2=F and fg.

References

[1]C. Babbage, Essay towards the calculus of functions I, Philos. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. 105 (1815) 389423.

[2]U.T. Bödewadt, Zur iteration reeller funktionen, Math. Z. 49 (1944) 497516.

[3]D. Głazowska, J. Matkowski, Subcommuting and commuting real homographic functions, J. Difference Equ. Appl. 22 (2016) 177187.

[4]M. Kuczma, On the functional equation φn(x) = g(x), Ann. Polon. Math. 11 (1961) 161175.

[5]M. Kuczma, B. Choczewski, R. Ger, Iterative functional equations, in: Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, Vol. 32, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990.

[6]L. Liu, W. Jarczyk, L. Li, W. Zhang, Iterative roots of piecewise monotonic functions of nonmonotonicity height not less than 2, Nonlinear Anal. 75 (1) (2012) 286303.

[7]S. Łojasiewicz, Solution générale de l’équation fonctionelle f(f(···f(x)···)) = g(x), Ann. Soc. Polon. Math. 24 (1951) 8891.

[8]N. Mcshane, On the periodicity of homeomorphisms of the real line, Amer. Math. Monthly 6 (1961) 562563.

[9]A. Smajdor, On some special iteration groups, Fund. Math. 82 (1973) 6774.

[10]M.C. Zdun, Note on commutable functions, Aequationes Math. 36 (1988) 153164.

[11]M.C. Zdun, P. Solarz, Recent results on iteration theory: Iteration groups and semigroups in the real case, Aequationes Math. 87 (2014) 201245.

[12]W. Zhang, P.M. functions, PM functions their characteristic intervals and iterative roots, Ann. Polon. Math. 65 (1997) 119128.

Acknowledgements

Declaration of Competing Interest: The authors declare that they have no known competing financial interests or personal relationships that could have appeared to influence the work reported in this paper.The publisher wishes to inform readers that the article “Subcommuting and comparable iterative roots of order preserving homeomorphisms” was originally published by the previous publisher of the Arab Journal of Mathematical Sciences and the pagination of this article has been subsequently changed. There has been no change to the content of the article. This change was necessary for the journal to transition from the previous publisher to the new one. The publisher sincerely apologises for any inconvenience caused. To access and cite this article, please use Murugan, V., Kumar, M.S. (2019), “Subcommuting and comparable iterative roots of order preserving homeomorphisms”, Arab Journal of Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 26 No. 1/2, pp. 203-210. The original publication date for this paper was 31/10/2019.

Corresponding author

Murugan Suresh Kumar can be contacted at: sureshkumarmsu2009@gmail.com

Related articles